Lecture 1: Aristotle on
Rhetoric.
I. Rhetoric, in the most
general sense:
comprehends all those elements in communication apt or meant to
achieve a determinate effect at the receiving end of communication by using
means other than the truth. That effect is called persuasion and can consist in
a belief (believing the truth), a confirmation, a decision, an appreciation and
many more.
Communication: a message from
a sender to a receiver. ‘Sending out’ at the sending end, ‘uptake’ at the
receiving end. What is sent is the message. Usually thought
to consist in a meaning and a signifier, something that carries that meaning.
Why exclude truth and, more
generally, normative validity, from the rhetorical means? If the sender tries
to persuade me by, simply, the truth, then he does not try to persuade me via
specifically rhetorical means. If I accept what the other is saying simply
because I am convinced that it is the truth, then I am not persuaded by
rhetorical means. Rhetoric is concerned with ‘how’ something is expressed or
put. Truth concerns a ‘what’-question. Rhetoric concerns a ‘how’-question. Or
does it?
Two radically differing
opinions about rhetoric:
One says: there is no such
thing as truth independent from how things are expressed and held. Just before
Aristotle the Sophists thought exactly that. The Sophists said: Whatever is
held as true is true. We can persuade anyone of everything, using the right
means of persuasion. Aristotle opposes them.
The other opinion says:
Rhetoric is or ought to be unpersuasive under all circumstances. The only thing
that counts is ‘the fact of the matter,’ truth, the ‘best.’ Truth and the best
are independent from the way they are being expressed and the same however they
may be expressed. Wherever people accept things because of the specific ways in
which they are presented to them (the ‘how’), there that acceptance is
inadequate. They hold what they hold for the wrong reasons. All rhetoric is
perturbation and deception. Aristotle does not agree with this view of rhetoric,
either.
Aristotle thinks rhetoric is
indispensable and a useful tool to get things across. But because of its
deceptive potential, it needs to be handled with care. There is some such thing
as independent truth. But not all questions find answers in just one ‘fact of
the matter.’ And it may sometimes be difficult to decide what is true or right.
Most importantly: truth and the best may receive help from adequately used
rhetoric – i.e.: good argument (compare Rhet 1355a,
I.1.14).
Rhetoric, in the comprehensive
sense of persuasive communication, is ubiquitous. It is not confined to speech,
which is just the verbal form of communication, and even less to public
speaking. Pictures use and have their own rhetoric. Ads. Gestures, expressions, ways
of dressing, make-up . . .
II. Zooming in on
Aristotle:
Narrow
scope: public speech. But significance way beyond that scope.
Rhetoric already there. An art/craft (tekhne;):
A good speaker has specific goals (persuasion), and knows how to use the means
towards that goal. Where there’s an art, it can always be performed in better
or worse ways. But no systematic theory of the art.
Aristotle
writes a practical treatise: How to be a good public speaker, how to evaluate
speech at the receiving end. For that purpose he analyzes the practice. Note
how Aristotle thinks about things: He analyzes them.
Analysis:
He finds things in a state, in which they appear “clear and plain to us,” also
because we know how to go about it. But things are really “compounded” in everyday
use. Which means: we do not have a clear conception of them, of their
significant elements, and how they work together. Analysis – a form of thinking
– takes these things apart into their essential elements. The undifferentiated
will then be differentiated in the right way, the item will be known only after
analysis (Compare Physics, 184a).
Rhetoric
is an art. Arts are defined by their function. Rhetoric is the art: “to see the
available means of persuasion in each case.” As a consequence Aristotle sets
out to analyze rhetoric in such a way that he helps us ‘see the available means
of persuasion.”
Why is
the function of rhetoric not described as ‘to persuade?’ Because Aristotle
distinguishes the analysis and teaching of the art (‘know-how’) from the purpose
of the craftsman who uses the art (‘what for’). Arts are defined by function.
But they consist in the things one needs to do and can do, in order to fulfill that function.
What is
it ‘to persuade?’ To change or otherwise influence the
attitude of a hearer by using communication (speech, images, sound, gestures;
expression and personal presentation).
Species
of attitudes: beliefs, held values, what one thinks is
right or wrong, feelings and dispositions towards things.
Presupposition:
Hearer neither already persuaded, nor immune to persuasion.
The
factual and normative aspects: Hearers actually respond to these means. They
are persuaded because the speaker is credible, succeeds in making them feel
good about the issues, present convincing arguments. But Aristotle also thinks
that it is right to let oneself be influenced by someone who presents the right
qualifications for being followed in a given subject matter. He even thinks
that the right kind of feeling about an issue is a reason for being favorably
disclosed towards it. He certainly believes that a good argument represents a
good reason. Think about possible misuse of the normative assumptions, and how
to counteract them!
The
means of persuasion is
‘speech’ – short for the medium of communication used to
persuade. Now we may be able to recognize a good speech when we hear one. But
this is “compounded” in our mind and in that of the speaker. So analysis is
necessary. Analysis distinguishes those elements most important for the
attainment of the goals of speech, i.e. persuasion. The “means” of persuasion
attach to these elements.
Elements
of speech: Speaker, hearer/audience, subject matter, spoken language, ways of
expressing subject matter in spoken language. The means of persuasion in general
are ways of fashioning some of these elements in an effort to persuade the
hearer/audience.
Those
that are anchored in the speaker are ethos, the character of the
speaker. Those that attach to the audience affective disposition towards the
issues are pathos, try to influence the
emotional state of the hearer. Those that attach to the way of presenting the
subject matter as rationally motivated are logos, arrangement and
presentation of subject matter.
III. Pisteis/Means of Persuasion
Ethos
(1356a; I.2.4):
Positively: character traits, personal representation that persuade people to
adopt or accept or endorse the speaker’s opinions, proposals or evaluations.
Which traits will undermine a speaker’s appeal to character? Credence/credibility is the general trait:
the speaker is a person who is worthy of credence (as concerns this subject.)
Aristotle: practical intelligence (phronêsis),
a virtuous character, and good will. My examples: experience, honesty,
expertise, thoughtfulness, authority, previous good advice, authoritativeness
(?), determinacy (?), be loved by audience (?). And
the opposites: inexperience, dishonesty, rashness, insecurity, hestitation, disagreeable, hated by audience,
. . . Important: different qualities of speaker will be differently
significant for issue: political decision, personal advice, expert witness,
estimate, etc.
An
example from Bacon, The Great Instauration, “Preface:” Suppose you were
proposing a revolutionary break in the way of doing science to your readers.
Many of the things scientists believe and methods they follow would not be
valid if your proposals were adopted. You need to count on extraordinary
resistance to you proposals. How would you present yourself, to increase the
credence of your proposals? What kind of perception might damage your
credibility? You will not be able to claim expertise or experience in the
subject matter ‘new science.’ It will not do to present you as honest. Nor will
it be good insist on your successes in different domains, like statesmanship,
martial skills, proven leadership. You may want to insist on the care that
characterizes you; on your own initial hesitation to deviate from common paths,
you may want to emphasize your lack of ambition.
Pathos: “Hearers are led to feel emotion
by the speech” disposing them favorably or unfavorably towards a subject matter
or issue (1356a, I.2.2 and I.2.5).
Some
examples from Aristotle: anger/calmness (of speaker, towards others or issues);
belittling/aggrandizing (of him-/herself, others, issues and problems); feeling
friendly towards/feeling inimical; fear of/confidence (in speaker or issue);
pity; indignation; envy.
Example from Bacon, The
Great Instauration, “Preface:” Suppose, again, you were proposing a
revolutionary break in the way of doing science to your readers. Many of the
things scientists believe and methods they follow would not be valid if your
proposals were adopted. You need to count on extraordinary resistance to you
proposals. What emotions would you like to arouse in your reader? Which
emotions would you like to avoid? Avoid, perhaps, fear of uncertainty, love for
tradition and the gradated, comfort of familiar. Use, perhaps, curiosity,
disappointment with failures of what you want to replace, depict or promise
grandiose achievements of the new ways; belittle the old; etc.