Lecture 4

 

Causality and the four causes.

 

I. Causality for us:

 

We think of causality as a link between causes and effects. The link between the two allows us to bring about the cause, and thereby bring about the effect. Causes, in this view, are triggers (naively): Striking the match in order to light the match. The striking against the right surface is the cause for the lighting of the match. Causal explanations explain effects. We explain an effect if we are able to appeal to a law according to which whenever the cause occurs the effect will follow or co-occur.

 

Presupposed in such explanations, as well as in the possibility to use a causal nexus is the fact that we hold stable the environment of the cause, and maintain favorable conditions in it. We want to light a match. We not only need an appropriate surface, but the right kind of strength in striking, under conditions where there is not too much wind, the surface and the match are dry, etc. The law we use says that the chemical substance at the head of the match ignites when it reaches a certain temperature. Explanation and use of the match to obtain fire coincide: whenever we have a scientific causal explanation we can use it to bring about the effect, by bringing about the cause, and to guarantee the necessary and appropriate initial conditions. Our everyday understanding of causality is effectuating causality. It links things, conditions and events with events in the bringing-about way. When someone asks: ‘why did such-and-such occur?’ we first think of searching for a cause in this sense.

 

II. Causality for Aristotle

 

‘Causality’ is our word. Using “cause” as a translation for Aristotle’s ‘aitia’ and ‘aition’ we need to treat our word as if we were free to give to the term the meaning it may have had for Aristotle. Instead of “cause,” “type of explanatory factor” (in Ackrill: Aristotle the Philosopher, p. 36) would be better, because it is more open. He starts with a question that is different from our modern question ‘why did such-and-such occur?’

 

Aristotle asks:  ‘On account of what?’ (194b20). And he thinks that it is a question of knowledge or, in an other translation, of science. (Not all questions are asked for knowledge). Everything that can meaningfully figure as an explanatory factor qualifies for ‘aitia.’

 

‘On account of what?’ is an incomplete version of Aristotle’s question for it does not specify two things that belong to a question. The first thing: It does not say where we should turn to answer the question. About what kind of item is the question ‘on account of what?’ being asked? It is, as we by now expect, primarily asked about individual substances. They are the items we are to explore looking for an answer to Aristotle’s question. We will focus on things, living beings like animals and plants, people and action. Our more complete question is now: ‘On account of what is this item . . .?’

 

But this is still incomplete. For we have not specified what it is we want to know. Without this element a question is unanswerable. What exactly are we asking about the item? The missing element specifies the direction of the question. It determines what counts as the right answer. Our own question ‘why did such-and-such occur?’ does this by asking for the ‘why’ of an ‘occurrence.’ Its implicit understanding is that we want to know what preceded the effect in such a way that it was sufficient to bring about the effect in the specific environment (initial conditions).

 

Now, Aristotle thinks that accounts come in several kinds of respects. He asks: ‘On account of what is this item . . .?’ – and then goes on, filling the blanks with the item, the state of affairs or the condition that is responsible for the item, more precisely: for the specific aspect of the item to be explained:

 

‘On account of what is this item a such-and-such?’ (This will be the formal cause)

‘On account of what is this item constituted by/as such-and-such . . .?’ In our words: ‘what does it consist of?’ (This will be the material cause)

‘On account of what has this item come about?’ or:  ‘Who or what is the source out of which this such-and-such has come?’ (This will be the efficient cause)

On account of what is this item useful for the end such-and-such?’ ‘What kind of end has this item been meant to achieve?’ (This will be the final cause).

 

The general form of Aristotelian causal analysis is:

B: something about the object that is to be (causally) accounted for;

A: that which is the giving of the account;

C: the item that is the object of the account.

 

An account for B in C.

Applying the medication (A) accounts for recovery from illness (B) in Cleisthenes (C)

 

Here, a patient (= C, the object of the account) has been healed from an illness (B = the fact that is being accounted for). A doctor had prescribed medication that has been used by the patient. What accounts for the change from illness to health in that patient? It is in part accounted for by the action of the doctor (= A; one of the possibilities of  efficient cause) and the power of the medication (= A; another possibility of efficient cause). The patient took the medication because he wanted to overcome the illness (final cause). The patient contributes to this effect his/her capacity to be healed, i.e. to be receptive to the intervention of the doctor and the impact of the medication. He changes from the (accidental) form ‘sick’ to the accidental form ‘healthy.’ (Sickness and health are certain ways of the body to be organized and to function). The formal cause is before all what the doctor wants to establish as the actual form, namely ‘illness’, and then what the condition of the patient “would be,” the new form to be acquired in the change. This is ‘health’ or, more specifically: the disappearance of the unhealthy form.

 

III. The four main causes:

 

A synopsis (partly drawing on Stanford Encyclopedia for formulations):

 

The material cause: that from which something is generated or ‘out of which’ it is formed or made, that of which the thing is constituted (the bronze of the statue, the flesh and bones of the human body, the subatomic particles of an atom, the letters in a word).

The formal cause: the structure which the matter realizes and in terms of which the matter comes to be something determinate, e.g., the Hermes shape in virtue of which this quantity of bronze is said to be a statue of Hermes, the soul that animates a body; a certain ratio of sound-wave frequency for pitch (194b28).

The efficient cause: the agent responsible for matter coming to be informed, that out of which comes the item we want to explain. (The sculptor who shaped the quantity of bronze into its current Hermes shape, but also his/her art. The form of the tree-to-become in the seed for the tree, but also the tree that produces another tree by providing the seed. The motion of the continental plates for earthquakes and volcanoes; the organization of a musical piece for our pleasure listening to it).

The final cause: the purpose or goal of the compound of form and matter, e.g. the statue was created for the purpose of honoring Hermes. The tree has the (inbuilt) purpose to grow into a mighty exemplar of its species and to contribute to the survival of its species.

 

The Material cause (194b23).

 

Let’s take the statue, an artefact, due to human activity. It is made from bronze. It is also constituted by bronze. It consists of bronze. Checking for what counts as material, you select a form and you ask, how, in what, through what that form is realized. For the statue: that which, relative to the form of that statue, ‘realizes’ that form; that which, relative to the form the item has by being that statue, ‘fills’ that form. Suppose it is a statue of Aristotle that serves as a  monument at Stagira (the city he is from). Then you ask: What is the matter of this monument? Then the answer is not” ‘bronze.’ Aristoteles is the matter of this monument. ‘Material’ is not just matter in the sense of ‘the stuff’ or ‘substance’ that constitutes the thing. It is that, which realizes the form. This is the dependence on form

 

But, in a different way matter is also independent from form. The same generic form can  ‘materialize’ in different ways: the generic form ‘bed,’ when realized, can then be out of wood or metal, its support a mattress or water. Similarly for the same individual form: this statue of Aristotle has first been ‘out of’ plaster, then out of wax, then out of bronze.

 

What, then, does a material account account for? How does it help us understand the statue? Q: How does this answer the question: On account of what is this statue the statue it is? We partly understand the thing when we know what its material and its constituents are. Knowing that it is ‘of bronze’ lets us know how it has been made or would be made, how we need to deal with possible decay or the desire for destruction, what we need to do to make a thing like that. It also helps us understand the statue aesthetically. Had the shape of Aristotle been made from marble or wood, Aristotle would appear very differently because he would have emerged through subtraction (compare 190b6). The shape of Aristotle would be very different.

 

In addition, a material account contributes to an explanation of change. Knowing the matter of a thing due to nature allows us to investigate one of the internal principles of change in that thing. (Recall, that this is the characteristic of things ‘due to nature,’ and that all artefacts will ultimately also include things ‘due to nature.’) The material cause is therefore a major lead as to how the item may have come about through transformations of the matter, and how it might change or stop to be that thing, equally by change in its material basis. It is also an important lead when we ask, how the item holds together and inquire into what holds it together. The matter that realizes a form is thus one of the sources of change.

 

Important: What counts as matter realizing a specific form may in turn be a complex kind of thing. Assume that there is a brick in the wall of the house. It belongs to the matter of the house. But the brick is another artefact, combining form and matter. This does not prevent the brick from being matter relative to the house. Reason: to be matter is to be in the function of matter relative to something that is form, and to be united as matter and form in that reality. Matter and form are relative notions. They call out for each other. You need to hold on to the form of something when you try to determine its matter. You need to hold on to something that counts as matter when you try to determine what the form is of some item.

 

The formal cause

 

First: what counts as form? We first think about form in visual ways: the shape of what we see, triangular, roundish, square, irregular, spherical, conical, cubic, erratic. Structure next: the form of a crystal or a snowflake, what is rendered by the map is a selective pattern of a landscape or an order of a city. Structures are not just visual. They concern all kinds of organizedness. It takes us to the form of artifacts and living beings. The form of the house is open, but it is subject to the function of offering permanent shelter to, let us say, human beings. Shelter dictates that there be elements that protect those in it against weather, temperature. But there must also be space for dwelling and the human activities that belong to dwelling. The form of a house can be described by pointing to those functions that are necessary for an artefact to be able to be a house: what “would be a house!” The form of a specific house would be a description of those concrete elements that fulfill the necessary functions: a brick wall in a Midwestern city, wooden beams and drywall in CA, a wall from snow and ice for an igloo. Structure is form as organizedness, and holds for houses, institutions, states, living bodies. (It is sometimes hard to distinguish organizedness from the matter in which the form is organized.) A final element of form: Also belong to the form the forces that stabilize shape or structure, especially in cases where what counts, as matter does not fall into the form all by itself. The forces that bind the sub-atomic particles into the unit of the atom would as much belong to the form of the atom, as the soul, because it is the element that enlivens the body and makes the different parts of the organism do their jobs. The soul is a dynamic principle that causes the substance ‘living body’ to be. It is ‘form’ relative to the ‘matter’ that are the organs because it forces them into the dynamic order of the ‘living body.’

 

 

Account for the form ‘face!’ Account for the constituents of the picture by invoking the form ‘face!’ 

 

 

This allows us to better see how form can be a type of explanatory factor. One kind of explanation is linked to the fact that the form tells us what would count as a thing of kind such-and-such. What has the form of an apple, is or can be an apple. (It is an apple if the form is realized in the right kind of way). This form is not just the shape. It is also the structure, or organizedness of its matter. I want to think that taste and smell also belong to the form of an ‘apple.’ Another explanatory element is that often we can point to not entirely trivial features that explain what the form is, and why it is the form it is. (The octave example; the Smiley example.) A third explanatory use is both theoretical and practical: Knowing what the form is, we may be able to detect in other things their ability to serve as matter for that form: the bricks, through their stability and the possibility to stack them neatly are possible matter for a wall, and thereby for a house. They can be used to bring about that form. Or: Knowing what the form is we may bring it about in order to achieve something through it. We may build houses to shelter the homeless.

 

The efficient cause

 

It is the “source of change or the staying unchanged” of the item (194b30). In the most direct way, and for things that are being made by a maker (houses, beds, statues). How about nests and spiderwebs? How about leaves, flowers and seeds? The spiders and birds may not be ‘makers’ in the sense that we are makers of the artifacts we make to serve our purposes. But it is still the case that the nest and the web ‘come out of them. It already begins to appear that a personal or rational maker is not required for the source. But the seed also qualifies as the efficient cause of the tree; and labor qualifies as efficient cause of strength (195a9). The reason is that they all are that ‘from which the change proceeds.’ Finally, the art that has contributed to the making of something (the art of the sculptor for the statue; the art of the doctor for the healing) is also something “which makes something of that which is changed” (195a6).

 

We are far from the modern understanding of causality. Most importantly, the modern idea of regular co-occurrence under stable background conditions is not what Aristotle has in mind. Control of effects through control of causes is not the interest that orients his reflection. His gaze is inspired by a will to comprehensive knowledge of how things hang together. A completely different idea of the goal of knowledge. I would like to add, however, that the Aristotelian idea seems to preclude modern science.

 

The final cause

 

(194b34).

You give an account in final terms by pointing out the end of the item, that for the sake of which it is, or occurs. What the item “is for.” (194b34). Aristotle examples: a walk for health; artifacts like drugs and surgical instruments for health. These are items that are made by makers for their purposes.

 

When we turn to things that are due to nature, human intervention does not make them what they are. Not all natural things have final causes. Not all are ‘for something’ (196b18 & 19) But many serve purposes. And all are, in one or the other way, teleologically relevant, at least in possibility. Thus the problem: If a certain herb is medicinal by having in it the power to heal a certain illness, is this power its final cause? More generally: for everything that can be used to end F, is F its final cause? We would have a tendency to say ‘no,’ if the final cause would need to enter into the way the medicinal plant comes about. Because we do not think that a teleological power, force or agency is at work to set up things in such a way that they can be used by humans. The Christian maker-God, on the other hand, makes a world teleologically oriented towards man.  (Compare Genesis 1:28 & 29: “And God said: . . . and have dominion over the fish of the sea and the fowl of the earth and over every living that moveth upon the earth . . . I have given you every herb bearing seed, which is upon the face of all the earth, and every tree, in the which is the fruit of a tree yielding seed; to you it shall be meat”). And Aristotle seems to think the same, without positing an agent of the Christian kind: “The ‘for something’ is present in things which are and come to be due to nature.” (199a8) Aristotle’s nature is a final cause. (198b10 & 199a17). This is not the view of modern science.

 

But if one views teleological aptitude as sufficient for accounts that use the final scheme, we could argue like this: garlic has antibiotic, anti-inflammatory capacity. It therefore ‘is for’ healing in cases of infection by bacteria. Isn’t this enough for a final account? The active component in garlic that is responsible for this effect could then be added into the equation when science finds it. We would add a possible efficient cause to the final cause. There is no need to posit a purposeful agent. Evolution allows for the genesis of teleological possibilities by chance. 

 

IV. Aristotle compared to Us

 

Aristotle thinks nature and explanation differently from us. His nature (in the comprehensive sense) is everything that is prone to change. Only things that are not subject to change are excluded. Things human, and things beyond the human domain and its culture thus fall into the same nature. All of them are also subject to the same forms of explanation.

 

His idea of explanation is comprehensive. A full Aristotelian explanation requires accounts in terms of all the causes. Aristotle does not yet adopt the narrow notion oriented by the idea of bringing something about that underlies (sic!) our modern notion of causal explanation. Structural accounts, accounts that show to what a form is due (in a sense that is not causal in our sense), accounts of an implicit function and possible purpose belong to a complete understanding of the world.

 

That world has an innate and basic tendency to change. Stability needs to be explained as maintenance. More importantly: change is continuous and connected: the underlying guarantees that there always something unchanging that traverses the changes and connects the opposites.

 

Aristotle’s concrete science has been made obsolete by modern science. His idea of the cosmos and of knowledge, however, marks a desideratum for our time. Dogmatic natural science has sometimes got into its own way, because it has closed itself off towards other paradigms. Evolutionary theory (19th century) and Ecology (20th century) are examples.