Plato_Lecture2

Eryximachus, Aristophanes, Agathon

 

Plato Lecture # 2

 

After the conventional praise of ‘Eros’ by Phaedrus, and the self-serving propaganda speech of Pausanias (homosexuality and Athens) – both predominantly normative, partial, ideologically and personally biased - we get into different water with the speeches of Eryximachus and Aristophanes. They offer different models of love, expressed in two different media: discourse and myth. Praise (encomium) is not absent but recedes into the background.

 

Eryximachus

 

Eryximachus makes a particular effort to divert the waters of love to his craft: medicine.

He is the first to present love as a dynamic principle: “it directs everything that occurs” (186B.3). The whole world is supposed to be ‘love’s labor.’ In fact Eryximachus does little to justify his sweeping thesis, in spite of the fact that he runs it through several topics: the body and, somewhat cursorily, through music, the seasons, the movements of the stars, religion, and the good.

 

His leading idea: in all of these domains, in short: everywhere, opposites underlie phenomena he addresses. Now those phenomena are in good order only when the opposites are brought into harmony. What counts as harmony is determined by the type of phenomenon: it is of one kind for the body (health), of a different kind for music (right rhythm and harmony), and still different for the seasons (temperate climate) or for the relations between humans and their gods (piety).

 

When the opposites are not brought into harmony the phenomena will be in disorder. Love is the regulatory principle, in fact a deity, that brings about order and disorder in the phenomena. Good order is the doing of the good kind of love; disorder is the doing of the bad kind of love. There are thus two species of love: ‘bad-love’ and ‘good-love.’ One is regulating. The other is deregulating.

 

Note that the model consists of two elements: on the one hand, there are the opposites. On the other hand there is love that is a dynamic principle acting on opposites. Good love binds the opposites into a well-ordered organization; bad love causes imbalance and leads to badly ordered, perturbed organization.

 

Problems:

 

       Eryximachus’ model of love loses the specificity of love, paying for the ubiquity

       of Eryximach’ean ‘love’ the price of saying very little about what love is for us.

       Is love for us a general binding and unbinding principle? What does that mean?

      Where is beauty? Where is erotic pleasure?

 

Why is an additional principle like love necessary to explain ‘good’ and ‘bad’ order?

 

What does it mean to be opposites? 

Opposites:  Normally we’d say: the organization, or more generally the thing whose order is at stake, determines oppositeness: an excess of one component damages its well functioning. When the same elements meet in nature, and not in a body, they do not necessarily oppose each other. Is it not more natural to think of pieces fitting together or not falling into a pattern (organs) than to say that every form of organizedness is an equilibrium of opposites brought about by love?

 

Love as regulator: Who or what are the subjects and bearers of this love? Can the opposites themselves be those bearers? Do they need, as it were, to fall in love with each other, to reach harmony and equilibrium, and thus to overcome their oppositeness? Why not think of a tyrannical principle that forces them into harmony (Hobbes!), rather than of love. Is Eryximachus’ ‘love’ a force that constrains something that would roam freely were it not for being bound?

 

Eryximachus adopts, analogizing, Pausanias’ moral distinction between the two kinds of love. ‘Good’ love works towards concord between opposites, ‘bad’ love towards discord. Love, as a consequence is presented as a regulating principle between antagonistic principles (forces, drives). It can work in a harmonizing way, but also in a way towards or even into discord. Why is ‘bad love’ the deregulating factor? Why not simply hatred or quarrel, particularly as the elements that are ‘out of order’ are said to be in opposition. If the harmonizing power – love – falls away, do the opposites simply act out their opposition? Eryximachus seems to work with two concepts of the elements in opposition. According to one of them, the elements are opposed and love is the external power that appeases them. According to the other, the elements have a natural tendency to fall into harmony. But then ‘bad love’ comes along and counteracts this natural tendency.

 

In sum: the model of basic oppositions brought into harmony by something external to the oppositions, and the idea that ‘bad love’ is a principle of discord in the cosmos are not coherently developed by Eryximachus.

 

It is also a bad idea of love because it leaves out the ideas of desire, attachment, and the role of beauty. We do not recognize our love in Eryximachus’ ‘love.’ Ultimately, he simply introduces a new concept of love, a concept that does not cover the phenomena we experience as love.

 

Aristophanes:

 

Basic ideas: Use of myth/story and irony as media. Articulates fundamentals of the ‘Erotic’ in a tongue-in-cheek way. Central model: erotic love is desire for a unity that is never achieved, but nevertheless brings about unions of different kinds (191D). Introduces the concept of desire.

 

Speech_of_Aristophanes (.mov file)

 

(also: http://video.aol.com/video-detail/speech-of-aristophanes-plato-the-symposium-189d-191d/1686803497)

 

 

The Myth is the principal means of articulation. Ideas need to be found by interpreting a story. Our present being and present dispositions shaped by ‘love’ are supposed to have come about in the following way:

 

- First phase: the three kinds of gendered beings and their modalities: purely male, purely female, mixed male and female. Each being has 4 arms, four legs and two faces. Genitals are also double. Each of the different kinds is offspring from a planet: male from sun, female from earth, mixed from moon. (Being round because one’s forebears are round pokes fun at analogizing argument. But, interestingly, there may be an allusion to the idea that the earth is also round!) Move like balls. (No intercourse and sexual reproduction in phase 1. Arch-beings are gestated in the earth like cicadas.

 

Change initiated by hubris of humans intending to attack the gods. Different scenarios. Zeus forms plan to cut them in two, and to threaten them with further division.

 

-         First modification and second phase: Halving of humans. Head turned around. Skin drawn over wound and refashioning of body. Upright gait. Decisive consequence for the origin of love: longing for lost unity and wholeness (191A.6). But that longing is not yet erotic longing, for it is as yet unrelated to sexual union, still unproductive and un-reproductive. Genitals still at the side away from the faces.

 

Further changed are triggered by unproductive effort to grow together again. Humans would die out. Zeus intervenes a second time. Then

 

-         Second modification and third phase: Sexual organs are moved to front and put into present places. Change of reproductive mode. Now “at the interior” and requiring sexual union of male and female genitals, instead of ‘out of the earth.’ Acting from a desire for wholeness and acting towards reproduction are amalgamated into one act. They are real merely in the relation between male and female, originally the mixed ‘whole’ being. Note the ironical distinction of homoerotic and hetero-erotic lovemaking, also letting the two modes appear as purely functional and biological differences without a difference in value (against Pausanias). First recognition of lesbian orientation, also as equal. 

 

Ideas about love expressed in the ‘genealogical’ mode of Aristophanes’ myth:

 

Different gender orientations (homo-/hetero-) are equal. Each fulfills specific social functions. For example: homosexuality generates politicians and “lovers of love.” (Opposes preference for male homosexuality), heterosexuality generates offspring.

 

The physical side of love is emphasized and recognized as worthy. ‘Eros’ is, among other things, pleasure in sexual union, both physical and mental.

(Opposition to soul-love as better part of love in preceding speeches).

 

‘Explanation’ and recognition of becoming stricken by love: we happen upon our lost other half. Also explanation of ‘this is the one and only …’ (193C.5)

(Accounts of what happens in lovers were so far missing or pointed to inadequate motives).

 

Explanation of desire for fusion. Hypothesis that, if we could we’d want to “melt together” as account of the deep bond between lovers. (Is this tongue-in-cheek?).

 

 

In my mind 2 major achievements in Aristophanes, (deeper in insight than Diotima’s position?): (1) desire in love is not originally erotic. Its goal is restitution and return to lost completeness. Desire is never satisfied in the act of sexual union; (2) erotic pleasure and its function in reproduction are add-ons. Explanation for joy in pure desire even without satisfaction of erotic component, and essential lack of fulfillment as features of love (192D.1)

 

Finally, the conclusion that praises love (193 C and 193 D). I read it as an ironical statement. Concept of irony.

 

Medium: the story is of course non-sense as historical account. But Aristophanes’ unlikely story carries more and better truths than the more discursive speeches. It would be particularly interesting to explore in greater depth how the theses are hung into the narrative, or how the narrative shows the theses.

 

Can Aristophanes’ theses be accounted for when the absurd assumptions of the tale are dropped? How would one go about doing that? Aristophanes’ myth catches some of the major tensions of love, but still over-rationalizes them by offering a mythical account. Does it make sense to think that erotic encounters and sexual union express a desire for fusion? Is the ‘coup-de-foudre’ – ‘love at first sight’ – adequately understood as relying on memory, and not just a sudden and unexplainable event? (Same for gender orientation).

 

Comparing Eryximachus and Aristophanes we see two models of love, that use two very different basic ideas for their model. But also striking: Plato sets up Eryximachus, the scientist as a confused and confusing theoretician, and Aristophanes, the artist and playwright, as someone whose wild phantasm is informed by a better understanding of love. Some bias!

 

Eryximachus, the scientist and craftsman, is a maker, and his model will reflect and be constrained by the purpose of making. That end is the understanding of illness and the orientation of healing. Bending love into this interest distorts love. The playwright is a doer and, indirectly, implicitly, unconsciously, a thinker. As a doer, the playwright is concerned with the motives, reasons, consequences of people’s actions, but also with the worthiness of and control over actions.

 

Agathon

 

Another playwright, but of tragedies. Also a follower of the sophists. Also supposed to be the most beautiful man in the group.

 

Agathon’s main claim: I am praising the God ‘Eros’ by, before all, saying what he is and, secondarily, saying what he gives us. Then Agathon throws around a huge number of value terms of praise: ‘Eros’ is the happiest, the most beautiful, the best. Young (meant as praise), delicate, dwells in the softest, possesses fluid supple shape, good looks, exquisite coloring of skin, settles where the atmosphere is flowery and fragrant.

 

Moral character, probably meant to exhibit ‘Eros’’ gifts: ‘Eros’ does not suffer or inflict injustice, promotes moderation, the most brave, seems to produce the best of everything, (poets, artisans, animals, …). Agathon ends with a list of everything that counts as good and claims that this is the doing of ‘Eros.’

 

Agathon’s success is palpable in the applause. Agathon spoke well. But did he praise the God? In one sense he did: He mentions good things, and attributes them to ‘Eros.’ Agathon praises merely in the sense of saying something good about ‘Eros.’

 

In his questioning of Agathon, Socrates requests more: “I thought you should tell the truth about whatever you praise” (198D.4). Question: Why should adequate praise depend on truth of things said in praise?

 

Truthfulness? Rather: Agathon and Socrates operate with two different ideas about praise.

Idea # 1 (Agathon): To adequately praise is to successfully praise. To praise successfully is to get the addressees of praise to think highly of the one who is the object of praise. Background: either there is no such thing as truth – or: truth does not matter for positive opinion about object. (the Sophists).

Idea # 2 (Socrates): Praise serves the purpose of making us rely on or want to emulate the being who is the object of praise. We are justified in relying or emulating only if what the one who is the object indeed has the qualities for which he is being praised. Otherwise the praise is empty and even dangerous. We may be relying on someone who ought not to be trusted. Or emulate someone and thereby emulating qualities that are not praise- worthy.

 

In his questioning Socrates brings into the open that the sophistic model practiced by Agathon replaces praiseworthiness with persuasion. Agathon has practiced empty praise. He just grabs worthy qualities and claims them for ‘Eros’ without in the least showing that ‘Eros’ does indeed have them. Note that by the same token all of the preceding speeches – Phaedrus, Pausanias, Eryximachus and Aristophanes suffer from the same shortcoming. They attribute to ‘Eros’ things ‘Eros’ does not have. Phaedrus and Pausanias have worked with a normative idea of what ‘Eros’ should be, praising ‘Eros’ for that, but did not show that ‘Eros’ in fact was what they said he should be. Love as we know it is not what Phaedrus and Pausanias say it should be. Eryximachus and Aristophanes, the other two, have worked with factual assumptions about love that are either assumption about something else (Eryximachus) or are invented and absurd (Aristophanes). (I think Aristophanes needs special discussion, because he reveals truths through telling an untruth). In sum: Socrates implicitly rejects all the preceding speeches for a special reason, and introduces a new constraint on praise: Praise must be based on truths on the subject matter supporting the praise. (This is not to say that the other speeches have said nothing valuable about love).

 

Problem:

Socrates’ alleged ‘proof’ that ‘Eros’ is neither beautiful nor good. The proof turns on the fact that love desires, and that a desire does not have what is desired. Conclusion: “love needs beauty, and has not got beauty at all” (201B.4) This apparently demonstrates that Agathon has ascribed to ‘Eros’ what ‘Eros’ is not and does not have.

 

Check Argument

 

PREMISES

love is love of something

(a) to love is for someone to love something

(b) love is the relation of someone loving something

love desires what/whom it loves

(a) someone who loves desires the something he loves

(b) the relation of love desires the something it loves

to desire is to need what one desires

to desire is to need what one desires

to need something is not to have it

to need something is not to have it

love is love of beautiful things

(a) someone who loves always loves something beautiful

(b) the relation of love is the relation of someone to something that is beautiful

(b’) the relation of love always loves something beautiful.

 

 

CONCLUSIONS

● “love has got no beauty” (201B.6)

(understood as: love does not qualify as beautiful)

 

(a) someone who loves does not have the beauty of the something he loves

(b) the relation of love does not have the beauty of the something it loves

(b’’) Problem -? -the relation of love has beauty/the relation of love does not have beauty?

(understood as: love does/does not qualify as beautiful).

 

 

 

Two problems in argument:

(1) Equivocation! Where is it? What are the consequences of the equivocation?

(2) Criterion for ‘being beautiful. Under which conditions would the relation of love, or the desire of the lover for the beauty of the beloved itself be beautiful? Does the lover lack beauty because he needs the beauty of the beloved?

Socrates beats the sophist Agathon at his own game!