Aristotle (384-322 BCE).

 

 

 

Son of a doctor. Sent to Athens at 17. Studies with Plato for a long time, but not chosen to succeed Plato as leader of Plato’s School (Academy) at Plato’s death. Called to Macedonia to be tutor of the king’s son, Alexander, later Alexander the Great. When his student becomes king and begins his conquests, Aristotle returns to Athens. Sets up his own School. Used to walk around while lecturing – hence the name: Peripatetic School. At the same time, Alexander conquers first the Greek cities, also Athens, then Persia and a huge part of the world then known to the Greeks. Sudden death of Alexander in 323. Athens breaks away from Macedonian domination, Aristotle flees. Dies one year later.

 

Groundbreaking work on pretty much all aspects of the sciences, theory of science, psychology, ethics, ontology, metaphysics and logic, rhetoric, literary theory. (The term “metaphysics” is due to the name for Aristotle’s writings on fundamental philosophical questions. Main traits of his philosophizing: Very abstract philosophical discourse. Great systematizer; tries to organize everything he finds into one huge order. Looks at the world as basically ordered by telos: everything behaves or ought to behave in a purposeful way. (Modern thinking is dominated by the idea of causal analysis). His ideas and his world-picture dominated thought and science until the Renaissance, albeit in a Christianized way. We will look at his ideas of soul (philosophical psychology) and how to live a good life (ethics), and nature (Physics).

 

I.                  Why be interested in the soul?

 

“For what is a man profited, if he shall gain the whole world, and lose his own soul? Or what shall a man give in exchange for his soul.” (Matthew 16:27)

 

Me, caring for my soul; my soul taking care of me. In this world. Aristotelian ethics is care for soul. For another world?

 

The concept is value-laden. Different sets of values lead to different models of the soul.

 

The Christian Idea of the Soul:

 

 

 

 

 

Soul that part in us we share with God. God’s spirit in us. Given to us from God, immortal, returns to a trans-mundane existence after our death (“Then shall the dust return to the earth as it was: and the spirit shall return unto God who gave it” (Ecclesiastes 12:7).

 

In this world the soul is human will, understanding, and character, i.e. unique personality. Feelings and desires belong to the flesh. Most importantly: the Christian soul is free. Free to decide to do the good or to do evil, not subjected to the senses in its decisions. Being the main agent and medium of insight and control, it is through our souls that we conduct our lives, our soul acting as a governing agency in us (St. Paul, Augustine). Much of that governing is over the body, which, through the desires of the flesh opposes to the control of the soul. It is up to us to be strong and to take the side of the soul in leading a life in accordance with the commands of god.

 

Each human being has a unique soul, given to her or him in the process between conception and birth (the Catholic church teaches that the soul is present from the moment of conception). It is our most precious good, and calls for moral protection of its being, as well as constant guidance.

 

From a transcendent point of view the soul is the agency that is responsible for the life we lead before God. Surviving our death, souls will be judged by God. If our life finds grace before God, the soul will gain eternal life in Heaven and enjoy eternal fellowship with God. If, on the other hand, the judgment is negative, the soul will be punished for the sins of our lives. (An older theology: hell).

 

The Buddhist Soul:

 

[Adapted from the article “Buddhism” in Encyclopedia Britannica.]

 

As individuals we exist in separation and limitation, both of which ground desires to overcome the obstacles, and desire is the basis of suffering.

 

Buddhism rejects the idea that the soul exists as a metaphysical substance, but recognizes the existence of the self as the subject of action in a practical and moral sense. Life is a stream of becoming, a series of manifestations and extinctions, without an underlying coherent agency. The concept of the individual ego is a delusion; the objects with which people identify themselves—fortune, social position, family, body, and even mind—are not their true selves. There is nothing permanent.

 

We can overcome the delusion of the mundane self and attain no self (an atman). But that means that we deal with the appearance of the self or soul. What we take to be our self consists of five aggregates or constituents (khan has): (1) corporeality or physical forms, (2) feelings or sensations, (3) ideations, (4) mental formations or dispositions, and (5) consciousness. Human existence is only a composite of the five aggregates, none of which is the self or soul. A person is in a process of continuous change, and there is no fixed underlying entity.

 

Two important elements of the complex and diverse Buddhist tradition: (1)We can overcome the delusion of self by attaining states of non-selfness. Yoga practices are a means towards this end. Not only can we exist in a state of non-self. We are also more enlightened beings in that state, closer to our true selves than when we move in the world of desire and identification with mundane values. (2) On the other hand, depending on how we live, we are reborn in different incarnations in other lives. This is of course difficult to conceive without assumption about something permanent that ‘underlies’ different existences.

 

Contrasting the Christian and Buddhist Souls:

 

The two religious attitudes – with their very different models of the soul, show quite neatly how basic notions depend on basic values of world-views: the Christian world-view modeling of the soul manifests the idea of a creator God to whom we are responsible in our lives and beyond. It also lets itself be dominated by the idea of a conflict in value between body and soul. The soul knows and pursues the good, the body is dominated by desires and appetites that fall on the bad side, and the idea that the soul ought to rule a recalcitrant and basically immoral corporeal self.

 

The Buddhist notion, on the other hand, conceives of our mundane existence in a negative way. It is thus let to see a problem in what is commonly called ‘soul.’ In setting up a practice of overcoming the negative, the soul is put into the role of that which is to be overcome, and the overcoming as the shedding of an illusion.

 

 

Aristotle’s soul

 

 

 

The soul is a well-circumscribed part of our whole being. First, everything that has life also has soul. (413a20: “that which has soul is distinguished from that which has not by life.”) Plants and animals have souls. As bodies are also found in the world that is not alive, soul must be the distinctive feature of life. But what are ‘body’ and ‘soul’ doing inside of the living unit, each of them present in that unit, how are they united and what is each of them there?

 

The naïve view: We turn to a living being. It is a substance in Aristotle’s terms: an independent being distinct from other beings of its kind and of other kinds. First we find a body, describable in biological term: the thing that lives. For some of the living bodies we find we will say that this body is inhabited by a soul that does what we ascribe to the psyche: it perceives, feels, remembers, dreams, thinks, desires, wills. We will, perhaps, also ascribe structural traits to that soul, things like character traits. These are NOT Aristotle’s ideas.

 

The Hylomorphic Model

 

Soul as form, body as matter:

 

“Now the soul is that by means of which, primarily, we live and perceive and think. Hence it will be a kind of principle and form, and not matter or subject.” (414a13)

 

“The soul must be substance qua form of a natural body which has life potentially” (412a19).

 

Body and soul are, in relation to each other, matter and form of the living being. This is Aristotle’s hylomorphic conception of man. Body is matter=hyle; soul is form=morphe. The soul is the form of the body of a living being. The body is the matter of a living being whose form is the soul.

 

What does it mean to be form, or to be matter?

Start with something that is a separate being of a certain kind. Aristotle calls it a substance. A tree, a snake, a human being are substances, but also a house, a knife or a lyra. Or start with something of another kind, because they can only occur together with a separate being: a feeling or an emotion like anger, a color like ‘red,’

 

Matter is that, out of which that something is.

Form is what we describe when we say what the something is.

 

Examples for form: shape and size (spatial form) of as figure, duration, speed, rhythm (temporal form), artifacts (house vis-à-vis brick and mortar), essential features, genre, inner order and organization). Anger – a sophisticated case (403a30): boiling of the blood as matter of anger, desire for retaliation as form of anger.

 

Form of process: continuous (, cyclical (of seasons); speed (of a moving object); ripening (of the change in a fruit).

Forming form: In general: the potential and tendency in things to assume a certain form (of water molecules to arrange in the form snow crystals; constitution (of a state); soul (of living beings).

 

Forms confer whatness, but also bind together parts and elements: the form of the sandstone rock binds together the grains of sand in the rock.

 

For the head of Aristotle shown at the beginning: Its matter is the bronze out of which it is made. Its form is ‘Aristotle’s head.’ (It shares that form with other Aristotle heads.)

 

A first comparison between living substances and substances that are not alive, juxtaposing form and matter in each case:

 

soul : body  ~ Aristotle-head : bronze

 

The analogy is from the point of view of form and matter: Just as Aristotle-shape is form relative to bronze as its matter in the statue, so soul is form relative to the body as its matter in the living being. Relativity: bronze is matter in the sculpture, but it can be form vis-à-vis molecules.

 

Form-matter distinction for living beings:

 

The bust is an artifact, we are not. Not yet, perhaps soon. We are interested in the form and matter of living things. That means that we need to look for elements that can count as form relative to the body. Now Aristotle’s decisive move: He lets himself be guided by the idea that life is the shared essential trait of all living beings, and that life is their shared form. ‘To be alive,’ ‘to be a life’ is our most basic function, and also of the world of plants and non-rational animals. (Note the process-indicating prefix “a-“ in “alive!). Aristotle’s idea and thesis: The soul is, or better includes, the complex system of life-constituting functions for the living being. Whatever actively contributes to confer life to living beings possesses soul character. Function as form. If all soul elements are absent, we do not have life. And all and only those elements that contribute in a forming manner to the conduct of life of a specific form of life count as soul- elements.

 

The biological body cannot be a living body without a soul. According to Aristotle, no live body is without soul. Attention: This is not the venerable animism that attributes to each living being an individual complete soul, assuming that the tree feels, perceives, acts intentionally, communicates with us, a soul that suffers when the tree is hit and says ‘no’ when the wind gets into its crown and shakes it. This is the attitude of the fairy tale (Lord of the Rings), of certain religions wrongly called primitive, and of our own ancestors. Aristotle thinks differently. More precisely: he thinks the issue, instead of basing his attitudes on faith.

 

How are body (matter) and soul (form) working together to constitute a living being?

 

Highly intransparent formulae: “The soul must be substance qua form of a natural body which has life potentially.” (412a18) and “The soul will be the actuality of a body of this kind,”i.e.of a “natural body which has life potentially.” And “the soul is the first actuality of a natural body which has life potentially.”

 

What is Aristotle saying here? Taken in abstraction from all soul elements the body of a living being is not alive. The body lacks the form necessary for ‘life.’ ‘Actuality’ is both that there is action – the action of the form on/in the body, and that there is something going on right now – to live is to be enlivened. Two ingredients, then, in “the soul is actuality.

But, in order to be able to be enlivened by a forming soul, that body must be apt to receive that form, just as the bronze and the marble must be apt to receive the form of the statue. This is why body, taken in isolation, has life “only potentially.” The body brings to the enlivening form the matter – an organization of flesh and blood, organs and body-parts. The “body has life potentially.” Without that potential and that actualization to concur, we do not have a living being. As a living being, the item with that form and that matter is a substance. What is it that lets that substance be that particular kind of living being, that goose, elephant or amoeba? We would use Linnaean criteria for distinguishing them from each other and refer, ultimately, to differences in body and bodily function. Aristotle thinks that it is the form, and therefore the soul, that is ultimately responsible, because the soul has formative power and function. So, the soul contributes the decisive element to the living substance: “the soul is substance qua form:” meaning: What kind of substance that being is the item’s soul-function. The body only lends its potentiality to the compound. (The conception lends itself to the idea that there could be an elephant’s soul in a mouse, or woman’s soul in a man’s body.)

 

(Note the prefix “en-“ in “ensouling” and “enlivening.” It presents the following verb as saying that there is an activity that brings about a result.) These formative activities are of the kind of a process and an activity; they are ‘actuality.’ The soul is therefore the actuality of a living body. ‘Actuality’ says two things: on the one hand, the soul is a condition for life; on the other hand, being alive is an activity first, and a state only second. The form-matter distinction is thus a first factor that lets the Aristotelian soul be distinct from what mind-functions are for us. For Aristotle, life=Bios is soul-activity!

 

What, then, is the body taken in isolation – and what does the soul do to the body when it enlivens its body? The body in isolation, considered without the soul, is close to the item that lies before us right after death, or better, in cardiac arrest: all the organs are there, everything that allows life-processes to unfold is in place. But the processes do not take place. These processes may resume, and if they do, the Aristotelian life-conferring soul returns to its matter and actualizes it. (Play this through for different stages of human gestation from conception to birth. Is there a likely stage or development for the life-conferring soul to be in place? Where would that be?). 

 

Can body and soul/mind exist separately?

 

The fact that soul is enlivening form to the potentially living body has an immediate consequence. Christian theology has answered he question right from the start in Genesis 2:7: “And the Lord God formed man of the dust of the ground, and breathed into his nostrils the breath of life; and man became a living soul.” But philosophy has been plagued by the question whether body and soul can exist independently from each other. You have heard that the Christian religious idea asserts independence of the two. And you will hear soon from Ann that Descartes thinks so too. The idea of separate existence or ontological difference of mind and body is dualism of body and mind, body and soul. Its opponents claim that body and mind do not have independent existence, and often achieve this by claiming that there is only one kind of item: either everything is material – both body and mind, or everything is mind, bodies and matter as well as soul. These are two monist positions: Materialism of the soul, idealism or animism of the world.

 

Aristotle sends them back to back, taking a position that is neither dualist monist.: “It is not necessary to ask whether soul and body are one, just as it is not necessary to ask whether the wax and its shape are one, nor generally whether the matter of each thing and that of which it is the matter are one. For even if one and being are spoken of in several ways, what is properly so spoken of is the actuality” (412b6-9).

 

No after-life for the soul after loss of the body it enlivens. I do not think Aristotle believes in an after-life in Hades, in form of bodiless shadow. All that can be said about the soul after death is that it is a potentiality for ensouling. And, as the uniqueness of the individual substance and the remembered trajectory of a life contribute decisively to the individuality of the soul in a living being, that individuality depends on the body. In other words: No continuation of individual soul, not even in the form of a lifeless shadow (Greek mythology), a soul that can be reincarnated (Buddhism) or a soul that can be subject to punishment or bliss in an after-life (Christianity).

 

Body and soul are two, because they play different roles in a living being. But they are not themselves substances, precisely because they cannot exist independently. They are not parts of the living being either, for they do not function as components. They are codependent: the body without the soul is a being that has lost its life and has lost the capacity for self-maintenance, also as a body. The soul that vanishes from the body is deprived from the matter that gives existence to it as a living soul. It is not the body that walks and the soul that feels. Both are activities of the whole being, in our case of the person. The person walks and feels. And walking and feeling both involve soul and body, in different roles.

 

Similar for the body: without the soul it is not alive. It is potential for life as long as the body is a ready recipient for the enlivening form, or is ‘ensoulable.’ The body does therefore not have special dignity after death.

 

Soul-body interactions.

 

Interactions: Behavior occurring between two agents or agencies in such a way that the action of one directed at the other is connected with the action of the other at the direction of the first: action1 (x à y) connected with action2 (y à x)

 

The basic form of interaction has already been discussed: the soul confers life to the body, which, in isolation is alive only potentially. The body in turn offers the potential for actualization of the whole being to the soul, which does not have reality without being embodied. The two are interdependent. When one occurs, the other also occurs. But we still have, as it were, two agencies, and therefore the possibility to analyze a phenomenon from the perspective of the body or of the soul. Anger, once again (403a30): anger – an emotion – is also boiling of the blood. But it is also desire for retaliation, and desire is a soul function.

 

The soul expressed in the body:

 

Nothing obliges Aristotle to think of the soul as an element that is ontologically spiritual, different from elements that are ontologically material. The distinction between form and matter is at any rate a relative and functional distinction: Forming soul is whatever is the form constituting element vis-à-vis something that is the formed – matter – in this connection.

 

His thinking is different from ours, tinted by 2000 years of Platonism and Christianity. But he thinks of an interaction here, between two agencies that play different roles in that interaction, whether they look to us as physical or as mental. We do not think like that. How can one think like Aristotle? First, he does not possess the chemical knowledge we have. Philosophically more interesting is the question: How can he even distinguish forming activity from formed form? If, as he says, the body is prepared to receive the form of life – the body is life potentially – how can one even distinguish the forming force and the formed recipient? Our chemical analysis does not do this. Indeed, it does not even have a model that calls for that thought. Our genetic perspective does exactly that, but only for growth and renewal of cells. Alas, also for the degeneration of aging. It looks as if we could think only in terms that distinguish soul and body as ontologically different, mental here and corporeal there, conceiving of the forming soul as if it were a sculptor who works on his material. Nature as clay animation!?

 

NOT Aristotle’s conception. To be form and formative does not imply being mental in the sense of ‘mind-stuff.’ The Bonsai tree shows in its appearance what its soul works from the inside:

 

 

 

[From: Finding a Soul in Bonsai. http://www.artofbonsai.org/forum/viewtopic.php?t=961

 

Part of the caption: “The Japanese have a word known as Kami. As far as I know I am about the only person who has chosen to associate this word with Bonsai. Other Bonsaists choose to use Wabi and Sabi when defining the quasi-spiritual aspects of bonsai. Kami is for lack of a better definition defined as spirit or soul, an almost personality that inhabits things of great beauty, power, and artistry. It is a force that almost gives a thing a life of its own that supersedes a tree or a pot or a sword, or a landscape.”

 

 

The distinction between an active, forming function in our plant and a passive, formed function makes sense if we make one important assumption: the body that is enlivened by the nutritive and self-maintaining soul of the plant is not just lying there, waiting to be ensouled, perhaps longing for it like Snow-White for the kiss of her Prince. The body is also recalcitrant. It has its own resistance to being kept alive and brought into its form. The form has to constantly overcome that resistance in maintaining that body alive and giving to it its typical form. Taken separately, the body is not just propensity to be ensouled, made and kept alive. It is also an item in its own right – potentially – and that resistance needs constantly to be overcome. We see it at work in illnesses, aging, in the deviations that can occur in generation. The idea of soul as enlivening form and body as formed life is therefore an idea that combines the idea of fit – the propensity of each to unite with the other to constitute a specific form of life and the idea that there is an opposing tendency in life – something that opposes being in that form. Only together do they account for life: Not ‘nature as clay animation,’ but: nature as antagonism of forces. Nature is the world of change. Its living domain changes as a consequence of internal antagonism. 

 

 

A comparison of soul features

 

- - - - - - - - - - - Aristotle - - - - - - - - - - -

- - - - - - - - - - - Modern - - - - - - - - - - -

 

 

Hylomorphism: body and soul functionally distinct but in interdependent relation.

Neither dualism (Descartes) nor monism (materialisms)

Dualisms: body and soul each have their

own being; may have independent destinies.

Monisms: materialism denies independent being to soul/mind; a certain brand of idealism says everything is soul.

 

 

Soul enlivens body; body gives reality and sustains soul in existence (gives ‘actuality’ to soul). Soul in principle not linked to mind, as we understand it.

Biological life is mind-independent, therefore not ensouled.

Mind-functions are ‘add-ons’ to life.

 

 

Hierarchy of basic faculties:
appetitive, perceptive, intellectual

 

Multitude and plurality of functions; related, but without systematic order, only partially ordered.

 

 

Soul-functions are active, enabling sources of performances, corporeal functions are

soul-activated; affective and perceptive soul-functions show double aspect: soul appearance and corporeal appearance.

Example: sight is due to the eye-soul making the eye perform its purpose, but depends on the eye being hit by object, and recording the object.

Hylomorphist: sight is interaction of eye-matter and sight-form.

Mind-functions are dependent on body-functions;

 

 

 

Example: sight either coincides with or is due to neurological processes in the eye, the nerves and the brain.

Reductionist: sight is but a complex of neurological events.