Core_09_Plato_Lect 2
Symposium: “Diotima Questions
Socrates” and “The Speech of Diotima”
The preceding speeches suffer
from untruth. They turn to only one aspect, leaving out others. Individual
points of view more than explorations of ‘love.’ Each time also Highlighting
interesting partial aspects of the complex phenomenon of love. All paint at
best a partial picture of love and base their praise and their recommendations
on this picture. The essence of love has not been articulated. Their
shortcomings damage their praise.
Now Diotima – the woman leads
the charge. Or: Socrates speaks as woman.
Diotima questions Socrates:
Diotima removes a prejudice
Socrates had: Love is neither beautiful nor good. It is an in-between and a go-between, a
dynamic principle between the realms of the atemporal and the temporal.
Diotima’s Speech Part I: Myth
of Love’s birth and nature (202B4-204B9).
Role of lover more important than role of beloved (204B10-204C8).
Speech part II: Object of
love, and what it means for lover (204C9-206B4).
Speech Part III.: Purpose of
love: give birth in beauty (206B5-207A4).
Speech Part IV.: Love has
desire for immortality. (207A5-208E2).
Speech Part V.: Normative
order of types focusing on one or the other kind of love (208E3-209E5).
Speech Part VI.: The ladder
of love (209E6-211A1.
Speech part VII.: The Idea of
love (211A3-212B1).
Socrates’ conclusion
(212B2-212C3)
The Idea of Love
My presentation moves through
Diotima’s contributions backward. Diotima leads Socrates and the reader on a
path that culminates in the ‘idea of beauty.’ The idea of beauty she calls “the
goal of loving” (210E6). ‘Eros’/love leads us upwards on a path through
different kinds of love for different kinds of beauty. The ascent is due to the
Idea of Beauty (211C.2). The purpose and essence of love is to lead us on a
trajectory through different kinds of beauty to acquaintance with the idea of
beauty itself.
The Idea of Beauty and Platonic Ideas:
Goal and highest point of the
ascent is “the sight of something wonderfully beautiful in its nature”
(210E.5-7). Beauty – pure – is an item of the kind of idea. The sight of the
idea of beauty is the sight of the most beautiful.
As idea ‘beauty’ is
“absolute, pure, unmixed” (211E1-2); “Beauty itself by itself with itself, …
always one in form; and all the other beautiful things share in it” (211B2).
Plato thinks there is a special kind of reality, different from the reality of
our senses and the mundane reality in which we live: the world of ideas. Ideas
are a special kind of existing item. Plato’s ‘Idealism.’
‘Idea’ ontology: Each idea –
beauty, the good, justice – is a unit that unites in it all the features of
those concepts, and nothing but those features. Wherever there is something
beautiful in our world – a specific form of beauty - it never is the
idea, because for each beautiful mundane item, there are mixed into it elements
that do not belong to beauty, and the beauty of the beautiful mundane item is
always in “another thing” (211A10). The beauty in the mundane forms is always
less than perfect beauty: relative (not absolute); impure (not pure); mixed
(not unmixed or homogeneous); plural (not “one form”); subject to change
(eternal and unchanging); incomplete (and not complete); partial (and not ;
compromised.
Ideas are what the many
things of which one can predicate the idea participate in: ▪horse▪,
▪triangle▪. That’s also called “universal.” But ideas are also
dynamic, active and passive principles: they are the driving force in all
beautiful things. All beautiful things share in the idea of beauty. Being
items, entities, units that are bounded against each other and do not depend on
others to be and to be what they are, ideas are “by themselves.” They are “with
themselves,” because everything, that Belongs to the idea is an integral and
necessary part of the form. Nothing foreign or inessential is mixed into an
idea’s being. More important than the ontology is the dynamic function ideas
have towards our mundane reality.
Dynamic functions of ideas:
Plato hypostasizes concepts (i.e. concepts as real beings). Idea-items into
active beings. In addition to being, ideas also do things! They let
things be what they are, and what we encounter them as: some as humans, others
as animals, some attitudes as love, others as hatred, etc. confer whatness to
the beings of our mundane reality. Those beings may be mixed, relative and be
otherwise imperfect. But each quality and each relation we ascribe to them uses
ideas. Plato thinks of ideas as forces, too: they come to and into mundane
things, giving to the things their essence and their qualities. They are at
work in us, orienting us, for example in the idea of the good. This is why the
things ‘share’ in the ideas (211B.2). From this point of view, love is the
drive in us to get hold of the idea of beauty. This is the ultimate goal. All
the minor forms leave the soul ultimately unsatisfied. (~Aristophanes!)
Diotima uses the idea of
beauty for several purposes in her speech. The idea as ultimate goal of love
organizes and hierarchizes different pursuits of love and assigns to them
places in her order of values. The closer to the Idea of love a specific love
and a specific type of beauty pursued through love, the more worthy that love
is. This hierarchy has been called ‘the ladder of love.’ A second
ordering function: love as pursuit of ideal beauty includes as more specialized
pursuits the two main subordinate purposes we pursue through love of beautiful
things, namely ‘to give birth in beauty’ and to pursue immortality.
Hierarchy of types of
love:
Going backward in Diotima’s
speech, we first encounter a hierarchy between domains. They are the fields of
‘body,’ ‘soul,’ and ‘collectives’ (cities and households). Different people are
differently drawn to objects belonging into one or the other of these domains,
and love means something different in each of them. Love for bodies, love in
body would be love for the beauty of bodily pleasure and offspring (208E3-5).
Love of soul – both the loving soul and love for beauty in another soul.
Soul-related beauty will lie in what that love tries to attain – wisdom, virtue
(209A5) The love for collectives will be the beauty in the “proper ordering” of
cities or households (209A7) guided by moderation and justice.
What organizes the hierarchy?
Different personalities are differently drawn to one or the other object of love.
Diotima clearly indicates that those who work on the proper ordering of cities
are the highest in rank in that hierarchy, those who work on the soul are next,
and those who find their love in the love of bodies are lowest. But, this is
how people are. They have different leanings and different competences. At this
place, the hierarchy is more a social ranking than an ordering of kinds of
love, although the rank is determined by what individuals love to predominantly
do/choose to make their main concern. The bases of the ranking remain the
things people are in fact drawn to. Arguments in favor? Quantitative argument-
offer more to share, work for more? Also a hierarchy in the good: the good
of/for the body is a lesser good than that of/for the soul.
One may wonder why those
concerned with the collective have a higher rank than those concerned with
having families and contribute children to the community. Diotima is not a
value-democrat. (Aristophanes looked like one!). Another problem with the
social ranking: It is not difficult to love the body and one’s family, to love
the souls of those in one’s social neighborhood, and to be concerned with the
right order of our communities. This is the ideal of the good citizen who is
also a good person.
The ladder of love:
A deeper hierarchy, more
normative than the social hierarchy of concerns and types of citizen. Diotima
seems to assert that one ought to love the community and its good order more
than the soul and its beauty (noble, well-formed - 209B8), and the soul more
than the body and the kinds of love anchored in the body. “The beauty of
people’s souls is more valuable than the beauty of their bodies” (210B7).
She even calls the body a
polluter. (211E2). This ranking, not of domains, but of loves themselves is
cast in universal terms: Everybody ought to ... Now it would be false to think
Diotima says: Let people not love the body, and love the soul instead. That
would be Pausanias’ device. The idea of love in its purity is not like an
imperative that says: Do this, and don’t do that. The idea of love determines a
trajectory, which the one who pursues beauty needs to run through.
The trajectory of the one who is initiated into the
rites of love:
First: love one body and
beget beautiful ideas there (210A8)
Next: several, then all
beautiful bodies.
Then: beauty in souls more
precious than beauty in body (210B6). Gives birth to beautiful ideas that will
make young men better.
Then: Beauty of/in activities
and laws. Beauty of body loses weight.
Next: learn to see the beauty of various kinds
of knowledge.
Next: Turning to all the
different kinds of beauty. Gives rise to ideas about them, their connections
and the place they occupy in the overall collection of beauties.
Final: acquaintance with the
idea of beauty.
Observations on the moves up the ladder:
The first move is an expansion, but also internal
transformation of love from step to step: the beauties of all beautiful bodies
is brother to the beauty of every other. The step is not towards abstraction –
the idea of corporeal beauty, the same for all bodies – embodied, let us say,
in a statue.
The expansion is pluralization: all the beautiful bodies
are differently beautiful. But, to the one who pursues beauty, everything that
exhibits beauty has the same attraction. The station on the trajectory towards
the encounter with the pure idea of beauty requires pluralization of one’s love
for the beautiful body. Don Giovanni? Or: interest in the beautiful body is not
desiring to possess it or be possessed by it! Overcome the “wild gaping after
just one body” (210B5) Two questions: (1) Does that mean that I will desire all
the beautiful bodies I encounter in the same way in which I desired just one?
(2) Does that mean that, because I love all the beautiful bodies with the same
kind of love that I will desire neither – ultimate sublimation together
with pluralization? In both cases something important changes. Loss of
intensity and dependence, gain of tranquility and independence? (Both?) Also:
The varieties of beauty in bodies is also the discovery that they all share
something: beauty. “From one body to two, and from two to all beautiful bodies”
(211C4).
What happens to the lower
states when the adept moves on to the higher stages? Or better: Once the
journey has reached its goal, what happens to the beauties and loves that have
been left behind during the journey? One can have a family, and be an
educator of souls, and be concerned with the good order of one’s
community. Looking at the trajectory we are examining here: When I move from
the gaping after one body, or from bodies to soul, or from loving concern for
the soul of individuals to concern for the order of the community, what happens
to the earlier stages? In the first place: Diotima says you need to move through the stages. That means that you
ought not to leap ahead to the higher ones before you have experienced the
earlier ones. The path matters!
Two possibilities for the
significance of the ‘lower’ forms, also two readings of Diotima’s speech.
A religious reading sees the ascent towards final goal as purification,
as leaving behind the lower forms. An ascesis of sorts.
Its message: Leave behind
what was loved, and the kind of love of the lower stage. The lower stage merely
transitory, a stepping-stone to the higher stage, an older skin, to be shed by
the person who grows in love. If that is Diotima’s meaning she propagates an
ideal of sublimation and renunciation: Sublimate your lower desires into higher
love. Give up the love and the satisfaction you may have gained from the lower
loves. A refined and transformed version of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ love articulated
in Pausanias. Love for the body needs to be overcome in favor of love for the
soul. Each time you leave behind a form of love that is more distant from the
idea of love. Your approach is initiation into acquaintance with pure love. The
way of the Buddha! Christian attitudes towards physical love. Diotima seems to
articulate the idea of sublimation and increasing purification of love when she
summarizes the “mystery of love: one goes always upwards for the sake of this
Beauty [i.e. the idea of beauty], starting out from beautiful things and using
them like rising stairs” (211C1-211D1). And “if someone got to see the
Beautiful itself, absolute, pure, unmixed, not polluted by human flesh or
colors or any other great nonsense of mortality” (211E1).
An integrative reading (mundane utopia, enrichment, sovereignty and
integration):
Think that what needs to be
left behind is just and only, each time, that element in love that does not
participate in pure beauty. That would be, in love of the body, the fascination
with just the body, or the dependence
on just one body: the “gaping after
just one body” in Diotima’s words. But maintain love for the body inasmuch that
love is not in the way of love for the soul and the community. Don’t let
yourself be taken over by passion, or lust, but allow ‘the right kind of love
for the body.” (What would that be?) What is to be acquired is merely to not let
any kind of supremacy of just one form or one kind of love be dominant and be
an impediment for the others: “not to be looking at beauty in a single example
– as a servant would . . . (being a slave he is low and small-minded) – but the
lover is turned to the great sea of beauty, and, gazing upon this, he
gives birth to many gloriously beautiful ideas and theories . . . (210D1-6).
Perhaps leave behind, in love for the soul the exclusion of the body and
disregard for the community. Each time, the thing to be abandoned is exclusiveness and dominance of the partial. But only that! Abandonment of ‘lower
loves’ vs. abandonment of lowly ways of loving in earlier stages of
love. The integrative reading overcomes the hierarchy of types because a person
who succeeds in integration will not practice just one of the mundane forms at
the expense of others.
Can we decide between the
two? Does Plato favor one? Should we favor one? I favor the mundane model, at
least in mundane practice, whereas the religious, transcendent model is the one
Diotima may dreams of, but at the same time deems unrealizable. Quasi-saintly
idea of love! But also devaluation of corporeal love in the religious reading.
Background to Christian devaluation of body. Idea leads and orients in right
kind of integration and understanding of partiality.
Criteria for love and
beauty
To give birth in beauty – to desire immortality
The initiation (by self or
other – comp 211C1)) that leads love/lead by love towards acquaintance with the
idea of beauty presupposes that all the stages and phases are - love. What lets all of them be cases of
love? The metaphysical answer: They all participate in the idea of beauty.
Unsatisfactory answer, because purely formal. For, what is it to participate in
the idea? What unites all the different form in such a way that they can be
arranged into a path along different phenomena or manifestations of beauty
towards the most perfect beauty and love?
Diotima makes two moves to secure
that everything she lists in her steps is a form of love for a beautiful thing:
(a) to love is to give birth in beauty (206B9); (b) to love is to desire
immortality (207A4). But first, she points to the fact that our language is
insufficient. “We divide out a special kind of love, and we refer to it by a
word that means the whole – ‘love’; and for the other kinds of love we use
other words” (205B5-7). Then she offers a formula that is meant to cover all
the different forms of love, and thereby brings them together under one complex
concept – something the other models were unable to do.
Diotima, after elucidating
the object of love, turns to the “real purpose of love:”
(a) “It is giving birth in
beauty, whether in body or soul” (206B9-10). Obviously to do something ‘in
beauty’ is opposed to ‘love wants/desires beauty’ or ‘love is wanting to
possess . . .’ (206A12). What does Diotima mean by the formula? Can love for
the body give birth in beauty? Is love for the body even giving birth –
literally understood – ‘in beauty,’ thinking of all the suffering and
mess that accompanies it? “Beauty,” Diotima says, “releases women from their
great pain” (206E.1) Are laws and institutions ‘beautiful?’ If so – in which
ways? To perform ‘in beauty’ must be compatible with messiness!
To give birth, birthing: to
bring something into the world that has not existed before, something that will
assume an independent life. Diotima rejects the idea that love is the desire to
possess, to get to possess the beautiful thing one is attracted by. The purpose
of love is not to possess, but to – generate, in the way of birthing. Taking
the term in a large enough sense, activities, laws, civic orders, but also
ideas are generated by us. Perhaps better: create? To generate in the way of
birthing is a special kind of generation. The transition is from the inside to
the outside, from gestation to delivery (in pain!), from delivery to nurture of
the newborn into independent life. The steps of Diotima’s ladder all have this
element. Not all handling of ideas or law is of the birthing kind. But at least
it is of the nurturing kind. Love is only or predominantly in the birthing
relation. To give birth, here, to bring something into the world, something
new, formed at the inside, and bring it to independent life and fruition.
The metaphor goes further:
Birthing presupposes pregnancy and pregnancy presupposes impregnation. Who or
what is the impregnating element that leads to pregnancy? The search for the
forms of beauty will not be it. Thesis: It is the Idea of Beauty as a dynamic
principle. Love, the mediator between the atemporal and the temporal, is
beauty’s way to come into the mundane realm. It desires for human souls to
become acquainted with it. (In another function the Idea of Beauty is also the
cause of the beautiful things we encounter and can learn to love.)
The thought that the idea is
the impregnating factor for our love for beautiful things is also a clue for an
understanding of Diotima’s thesis that love is not a god but a spirit, an “in
between” (202D14). The “shuttling back and forth” now
turns out not to be just between the mundane lover and the beautiful thing
he/she loves, but between the idea of beauty and the soul of the lover.
The two relations exist side by side, inextricably linked, and dominated by the
idea of beauty.
From beauty to the lover: The
idea of Beauty inseminates the soul of the lover with the interest in beautiful
things, and at the same time with a desire to acquaint him-/herself with the
form, the idea of beauty itself. This is one way between the idea and the
lover.
From the lover to beauty: The
other way of the “shuttling” is to learn to love everything that is beautiful
and thereby participate in the idea of beauty, and to learn that this is a path
towards getting a glimpse of pure beauty. This is why the messenger can be said
to “round out the whole and bind fast the all to all” (202E7). To be
‘in-between’ is to be a ‘go-between’ – moreover a go-between that serves as the
arm of the agents between whom it shuttles. They are the lover and the Idea of
Love.
(b) to give birth in
beauty. What does “in beauty” here mean? Footnote 79 on p. 53 of our text
seems to me to get things wrong. ‘In-ness’ is neither inside the person who
gives birth, nor the fact that a beautiful person is present. The “in” in “in
beauty” is like the “in” of “to believe in friendship,” or “to partake in a
rite.” In both cases the one who does something “in …” performs something that
places the agent inside the scope of something, here inside the scope of
friendship and ritual. We say: “he/she is all into …” The practitioner
of friendship inserts him-/herself into friendship. The participant in the rite
places himself inside the community that binds itself together by performing
the rite. The birthing of love is and ought to be inside the scope of beauty.
Beauty is thus a modality, and at the same time a value realized by/in/through
the birthing. How does one place one’s loving activity inside the scope of
beauty? By letting one’s loving be oriented, motivated and constrained by the
idea of beauty, pure beauty. ‘… in beauty’ is thus a mode of participation. The participation is in
the idea of beauty. How are the mundane activities of love-making, delivering a
child, educating an adolescent, practicing the tasks of a member of a community
participating in the idea of beauty? That is the case if and when these
activities are performed as steps towards the Idea of Beauty. Not every
activity that claims to love does that. Alcibiades, for example, seduces to
exert his power over Socrates. His ‘love’ would be love of power, for Diotima:
Love for the purpose of power, and therefore neither a case of birthing nor of
‘in beauty.’ Socrates, on the other hand, in the scene (219B3-where the two sleep
together under the cloak, corporeally together but not making love.)
But when is a love ‘birthing
in beauty?’ What are the criteria for an activity to be beautiful by “being
done correctly” (210A2 and 210A6)? Those criteria are never spelled out in
detail, also because they are supposed to draw on the idea of love, and there
is no clear image of that idea. Elements that come up here and there: Negative:
no self-interest; pleasure and satisfaction tied to beauty itself – a certain
‘formality’ as distinct from physicalness; in each field (body, soul,
education, community) that which ties together the units prone to be in discord
or distance: harmonizes them in communal
forms and rites (compare the formula from 202E7: “rounds out and binds all to
all.” Freud’s ‘Eros’); an element of mutuality and reciprocity (see Alcibiades
at 222B3, and recall Pausanias’ ethics of ‘justified conquest’ for contrast).
But also, in each of the ‘lower’ forms the simultaneous pursuit of the ‘higher’
forms – again documented by Alcibiades. It is because he could not conquer
Socrates’ body by using his, Alcibiades’ beauty as a bait, Socrates was able to
educate Alcibiades and tie Alcibiades to himself in friendship and make him
accept the status of disciple.
Diotima puts forward a second
purpose for love. “Love must desire immortality.” (207A4). An amazing,
counterintuitive claim. Immortality of the lover? Of the beloved? Of the
love-relation? Of the individuals, their groups, the species? Here, Diotima
seems to make a quasi-biological, at least a naturalistic claim: love, in
natures of the kind of life, aims at immortality. For individuals, immortality
is unattainable. But Diotima points to reproduction. Reproduction gives
duration to the species under conditions of mortality of specimens. Let us not
think along Darwinian lines, where species also originate and die out. (The
ancients did not believe that species were equally an ephemeral kind of item).
So, continued reproduction confers immortality to biological species.
But this does not seem to be
her point in 207D2-207E4. In her perspective the reproductive aspect of bodily
love is a renewal of the mortal individual
in his/her offspring. The idea of generations and their lines being a unit, as
it were, one long serial being, realized in instances that pass away and
renewing themselves. This is of course a line that can come to an end for an
individual serial being. But each event of reproduction could be understood as
manifesting the desire for individual immortality. (Compare to and contrast
with Aristophanes’ desire to return to original unity).
Diotima extends her idea of
immortality to knowledge and the pursuit of virtues, exemplified by seeking
glory. I do not think her argument is very persuasive, because preservation and
immortality are not the same thing. Preservation can easily by finite in
purpose and desire. Socrates, by the way, calls her reasoning “in the manner of
a perfect sophist” (208C2).
Summary:
In the bizarre form of the
‘ladder of ascent’ where (a) different types and different forms of love are
steps on a journey towards acquaintance with the Idea of Love, and (b) that
idea is at the same time an end of the journey and (c) the driving force along
that journey, and (d) an imperfect ingredient in each of the different forms
Diotima manages to make a proposal that, if successful, achieves a number of
things the other speeches do not achieve.
1. She gives a successful idea of ‘true love’ or of the
‘truth of love’ by anchoring that truth in the Idea of beauty, and the purpose
of ‘birthing in beauty.’
2. She organizes the disparate and seemingly unconnected
forms of love we have encountered in the text into one dynamic model.
3. She proposes a model that is normative and factual at
the same time.
4. Her model overcomes the gaps that separate ‘love
of/for the body,’ ‘love for the soul (‘Platonic love’ (?)), ‘love of knowledge
and wisdom,’ ‘love of one’s community,’ ‘love of self’ vs. ‘love of the other,’
‘male-gendered (self-control, other-domination) love’ vs. female
(other-nurturing, self-abandonment) love. She binds them together without
omitting and negating their differences.
5. She offers a clue for the understanding of the other
speeches: Each of them represents an idiosyncratic version of a form of love, from
the background inspired by the Idea of love, but distorted by conditions of
mundane reality.
6. She offers a basis for the evaluation of what in those
speeches is falling short or away from the Idea of Love and the right kind of
birthing, and what in them represents ‘giving birth in beauty.’ (Most of the
things my discussion has been critical of will also appear in a negative light
from the point of view of Diotima’s model).
Problems
I have with her:
(a) The leading end and value ‘idea of beauty’ remains undeveloped,
and needs to remain undeveloped given the epistemic status of Platonic ideas.
(b) The effort to bind all the forms into one model is in
a context that devalues bodily love. There remains an exclusiveness of the
kind: if you value highly the loves of the body you do not have the correct
relation to the other forms of love. My own inclinations: I am not certain I
agree with the hierarchy of values Diotima uses (e.g. soul over body); the idea
that strong motivation by one form must be at the expense of motivation by the
other seems to me to not be universally justified. A certain ascetism.
(c) There is something too smooth, overly synthetic, even
ascetic in the model as a whole, particularly visible in the religious reading
of increasing sublimation and renunciation. Tensions disappear in what she
represents as the natural and correct way of learning how to love. I can
imagine less demanding, and less hierarchizing kinds of integration.
(d) Where is the element of struggle between the
non-birthing and the birthing drives in us? Is Alcibiades perhaps appearing as
a reminder that it is not just the goodwill and accepted guidance by the Idea
of Beauty that promotes ‘giving birth in beauty’ but the very existence of the
ugly penchants when they meet the other tendencies head-on? That strife is the
medium of the journey, not following the voice of beauty in us or in the
leader? (210A8). Isn’t Diotima’s myth about the birth of love – this must be
the mundane varieties, because the Idea of Love’ is eternal and timeless – also
pointing in the direction of a positive role of just those elements Diotima’s
model downgrades? Mundane love is born from Penia (poverty, indigence,
neediness) and Poros (resourcefulness, the ability and cleverness to find a way
to achieve one’s ends). Does it not look as if Penia raped Poros in his sleep?
Diotima would readily consent that there may be poverty in wisdom and
resourcefulness in acquiring wisdom, the mundane in-betweenness thus playing
inside her scheme of values. But do those who have distinguished good and bad
love not have a point that bad love also needs to be integrated into the job of
loving in the right way?