Aristotle’s
Ethics. Lect 1 & 2
Aristotle (384-322 BCE).
Son of a doctor. Sent to
Athens at 17. Studies with Plato for a long time, but not chosen to succeed
Plato as leader of Plato’s School (Name of Plato’s School: Academy) at Plato’s
death. Called to Macedonia to be tutor of the Macedonian king’s son, Alexander,
later Alexander the Great. When his student becomes king and begins his
conquests, Aristotle returns to Athens. Sets up his own School. Used to walk
around while lecturing – hence the name of his School: Peripatetic School. At
the same time, Alexander conquers first the Greek cities, also Athens, then
Persia and a huge part of the world then known to the Greeks. Sudden death of
Alexander in 323. Athens breaks away from Macedonian domination, Aristotle
flees. Dies one year later.
Groundbreaking work on pretty
much all aspects of the sciences in particular biology, theory of science,
psychology, ethics, ontology, metaphysics and logic, rhetoric, literary theory.
(The term “metaphysics” is due to the name for Aristotle’s writings on
fundamental philosophical questions. Main traits of his philosophizing: Very
abstract philosophical discourse. Great systematizer; tries to organize
everything he finds into one huge order. Looks at the world as basically
ordered by telos: everything behaves or ought to behave in a purposeful way.
(Modern thinking is dominated by the idea of causal analysis). His ideas and
his world-picture dominated thought and science until the Renaissance, albeit
in a Christianized way. We will look at his ideas of soul (philosophical
psychology) and how to live a good life (ethics).
What is Ethics?
A body of prescriptions,
rules, values and conventions orienting our behavior. Guide us in
distinguishing what we ought to do (ethically right) and ought not to do
(ethically wrong), good or evil/bad, and how we ought to live. Important for
ethics: When do we act freely? What is agency? What are we responsible for? Why
should we be moral? What do we achieve when we are moral?
Normative: offering and
demanding orientation. But distinct from law, customs and mere social
conventions by not being valid through legislation, or merely observed
conventions in a given community. Morality: the concrete rules of an existent
or historical community or culture. Ethics: What is good? What is the highest
good? Most ethics make universal claims: Slavery is unethical. Examples: the
Ten Commandments. Aristotle’s excellences like courage, honesty, justice. The
idea that we ought to pursue the greatest possible happiness of all in our
society. The idea that we only should do what is universally acceptable.
Status today:
No clear notion in everyday
life. Blends into morality: Don’t lie! Don’t force others against their will!
Help those who need help. Don’t torture. Ethics comes to our minds when we feel
unfairly treated or wronged, or see something we disapprove of: That’s not
fair! Or: Madoff’s actions were deeply unethical. Ethics in the philosophical sense is not a
priority and an everyday concern, at least not in an explicit way. Things are
different for people who are religious. Most religions ask their faithful to
live by certain rules, and to conduct their lives in specific ways. Think of
the Puritans. Their whole life was guided by their religious ethics.
Philosophical ethics tries to determine, through thought, what is right
and wrong, good and evil, and to offer models on how we ought to, live and who
we ought to be and become. In modern times two dominant ways of thinking about
what is morally right and wrong. One school looks for basic rules, moral laws
of a comprehensive kind (Universalism). Its paradigmatic version comes from the
German philosopher Kant: Act only in such a way that you your wills and
policies are acceptable to every rational person as laws for all. The other
school starts from the assumption that we primarily act out of self-interest.
Each of us pursues his/her own happiness, understood as avoiding pain and
gaining pleasure. Regard for others becomes morally relevant to the extent as
their happiness is tied in with ours (Utilitarianism). Both schools try to
offer to us formulae and procedures that allow us to decide whether an action
we are considering is morally good or morally bad. Those who do the right
things will lead moral lives.
Aristotelian Ethics
Aristotle neither an ethicist
of moral laws, nor a defender of wishes and wants, nor someone who offers us a
formula that tells us which actions to do, and which to omit. Founder of a
third school: virtue ethics. Virtue ethics, Aristotelian style, urges us to
lead a good life, tells us that the good is the pursuit of happiness, and that
happiness emerges from the effort to acquire and to practice virtues or
excellences. Practicing a virtue we are and become excellent. Not using a
virtue on the occasion where it applies diminishes our status of excellence.
What matters most and
foremost is that we lead our lives in the right way. Actions and our intentions
enter only as ways and means to lead a good life.
What is it ‘to live a good
life?’
Seeking happiness by
pursuing excellence.
Eudaimonia – Aristotelian Happiness.
I start with a provisional
characterization oh Aristotelian happiness. It is neither the satisfaction of
all of our wishes and wants, nor social recognition (honor), nor the possession
of the means for acquiring what we desire. (Book I, chapter 5). Aristotle’s
happiness springs from “an activity of soul in accordance with complete excellence”
(NE Reader, p. 374, 1102a1 – not in the recommended readings). A specific kind
of pleasure attaches to such an activity. It is the pleasure that comes with
activities that pursue excellence. Book I, chapter 8). “Excellent actions are
in themselves pleasant” (NE Reader p. 373, 1099a21). There is happiness in the
action that is performed in accordance with excellence. But there is also
happiness in a life spent in the pursuit of excellence(s). Examples: Let
courage be an excellence. To act bravely in a given situation carries with it a
specific form of happiness: I have done the best I can do. To seek out a friend
who pursues the same kind of happiness I am seeking in my life gives me the
specific pleasure of engaging in an activity that is excellent, and that
contributes to make me (and the other excellent.) ‘Happiness’ translates
“eudaimonia”. The hint we can take from the term: It is to be ‘well-spirited.’
Excellence or Virtue – aretē.
A good life is a life that
seeks happiness by pursuing excellence. It is the “state of man which
makes a man good and makes him do his own work well.” (NE Reader p. 382,
1106a22). ‘Excellence’ translates “aretē.” “Virtue” is another
translation. We think of virtues as being prescriptive qualities: a virtuous
woman, very much in the tradition of modern moral thinking: one is virtuous
only if one obeys certain prescriptions and abstains from certain actions.
Virtues are moral prescriptions. This is not how Aristotle thinks about
excellences. In the first place, everything that has a purpose is something
that can be evaluated under the aspect of excellence or virtue.
Living beings and artifacts –
houses and knives - have virtue. The aretē of a house is to be a
good house, i.e. something that offers good shelter in a durable way as
distinguished from offering bad shelter and being haywire. Excellence is here
concerned with the evaluation of the item from the point of view of how well it
fulfills that purpose. Excellence is graded: things can be better or less good,
concerning the excellence of fulfilling a certain function. Excellence, in
general, is to be able to be evaluated as better or worse, always with respect
to its function. The good knife cuts well, does not blunt easily, resists quick
rusting etc.
For living beings in general,
excellence is related to their internal purpose or finality. Plants, animals
will be more or less good exemplars of their kind. The form that is active in
shaping them and drives their comportment is directed at making each one of
them be the most perfect exemplar of its kind, in all of the relevant respects:
a powerful tree, that resists atmospheric challenges, getting into the best
exemplar circumscribed by their potential. The ideal form – recall the little
oak tree – manifests the excellence of the thing. But form is not everything.
For the tree, function needs to be added: a powerful tree. Human beings share
in this purpose of aiming at the best possible exemplar they can become, both
in body and soul.
Zooming in on ethical excellence. Human excellence is
attached to that faculty of the soul that is specifically human: reason. It “is
distinguished into two kinds: intellectual and moral (NE Reader p. 375, 1103a4
and NE p. 376, 1103a17). Moral excellence, which interests us here, consists in
the better or not so good conduct of soul faculties, where what counts as
‘good’ is determined by reason, and where I act for the sake of that good.
Excellences are states, i.e. conditions of our soul due to actions we have
taken and attitudes we have acquired by choosing to realize our rational
potential as fully as possible. Typical excellences or virtues are courage,
truthfulness, practical wisdom or prudence, justice. Friendship is an atypical
excellence. Excellences exist in us by nature, but at first only as potential:
“we are adapted by nature to receive them” (NE Reader p. 376, 1103a24). They
are there, but do not develop by themselves: “none of the moral excellences arises in us by nature” (NE Reader p.
376, 1103a19. My italics).
Acquiring Excellence:
How do we get those
excellences, first only dormant in us? We first get them by exercising them (NE
Reader p. 376, 1103a30). Part of Aristotle’s ‘good life’ is therefore that we
learn what our excellences are and how to pursue them by doing, more precisely:
by acting in accordance with them. Important: This is not just learning
something, in order to be able, later, to do the right thing. Acquiring
excellences is itself already an integral part of leading the right, i.e. the
‘good’ life. In other words: you need not be truthful, brave of just in order
to be moral. It may well be the case that you have not mastered the subtleties
of an excellence, and are therefore as yet unable to practice the excellence in
an adequate way. But that does not matter. What is required is that you work at
acquiring the excellence. “By doing
the acts that we do in presence of danger, we become brave” (NE Reader p. 377,
1103b16).
We will all agree that
learning to do the right thing is important and laudable. But not all of us
will agree that working at learning is an integral part of being moral. For the
first time we see that Aristotle is not primarily looking at us being moral throughout,
on every occasion, and according to precise and strict criteria for courage or
honesty. What primarily matters is that we build the right kind of character. Ethos
is character and habit. Ethics is concerned with character and habit. Character
is a disposition to behave in certain ways, be it as a sincere person, be it as
an insincere person. Excellences – states of our souls, arise from activities,
and are ‘actualized’ in activities. Activity is decisive also once we have
acquired the excellence. No excellence is definitely acquired!
Habit
We need to distinguish
learning, acquisition and practice on the basis of having the experience of an
excellence. So far we have mentioned acquisition of an excellence. How do we
let ourselves be guided by excellences once we have learned them? (NE Reader p.
376, 1103a31) Big difference between the excellence of a knife and the
excellence of courage, justice, temperance, truthfulness, friendship or
practical wisdom. Once the knife has its excellence, that excellence does not
vanish by itself. (It does diminish through use.) The opposite holds for moral
excellences of the human animal. Our moral excellences, however, are
states/dispositions that fade, vanish or even transmute into their extremes
when they are not practiced. Reasons for this: (1) there is always some
resistance to be overcome against the choice and the implementation of the
right kind of conduct, (2) there also is the necessity to constantly redefine
the excellence in different circumstances. Most importantly: (3) the habit and
the habitus weaken and fade unless
practiced. We slowly lose the moral sensibility we have acquired through
practice. The virtuoso musician. (So, when Aristotle says: “Being habituated to
feel fear or confidence, we become brave or cowardly,” . . . “states arise out
of like activities” (NE Reader p. 377, 1103b16 & 1103 20) he is not just
pointing to learning.
Attitudes, background for action: The agent who pursues
excellence “must also be in a certain condition when he does them [i.e. the
actions]; in the first place he must have knowledge, secondly he must choose
the acts, and choose them for their own sakes, and thirdly, his action must
proceed from a firm and unchangeable character” (NE Reader p. 380, 1105a30).
Aristotle is articulating a thesis about what it is to have or to be in
the state of courage or justice, or in the relation of friendship. We are in
the state only insofar as we practice it, or are prepared to practice the
excellence when its occasion arises. We do not have it, or diminish its being
in us, when we do not enact the excellence. We are not a friend when, in
situation where friendship would demand that we behave as a friend (‘in
accordance with friendship’) we do nothing or even betray the one we call ‘our
friend.’ Of course, we can fail here or there, thereby just worsening our
status ‘state’) as a friend. But we cannot systematically or on crucial
occasions fail to act in accordance with friendship, without annulling that
status. In general: for excellences, being depends on doing. Being is a form of
becoming. Or better: we are constantly in the state of becoming brave, perhaps
also ‘more courageous’ or of ‘becoming friends’ or good or better friends.
And the other way round:
every case where there is an occasion for practicing a moral excellence, but we
do not do so, diminishes the excellence and contributes to a state of vice. The
process and practice has priority. The state of excellence is dependent on
practice. And, as the ‘good life’ consists of having excellences, the good life
is no more and no less than the practice of excellences – in the manner of
choices that aim at the intermediate. That said, the more we build habit, the
more it feeds back into future practice. A self-reinforcing activity and self-weakening
inactivity.
Reason and Choice:
What is the role of reason in
the practice of excellences? Excellences are ‘states.’ These are “things in
virtue of which we stand well or badly with reference to the passions” (NE
Reader p. 381, 1105b25). These are not states in the same sense in which a
substance is in liquid or gaseous state. Aristotle’s states are dispositions:
to be ready to behave in a certain way when the conditions arise that put this
state into action. Flammability is a state in that sense. The state of
excellences is our disposition to behave in certain ways when a passion pushes
us in a certain direction. (Alcibiades!). When do we ‘stand badly with
reference to a passion or, for with reference to a desire or appetite? We do,
when we let ourselves be overwhelmed by a passion, or driven by a desire. A
fine line separates ‘allowing to oneself one’s feelings’ and ‘being overwhelmed
by one’s feelings.’ To let ourselves be overwhelmed, or simply to be
overwhelmed – out of control from anger, driven to self-abandonment and
destruction by passion, (“Fatal Attraction”), too fearful to take the right
action against a danger, exploiting a friend out of greed – where this happens
we “stand badly with reference to the passion.” Why? Is it because the passion
might lead us to do stupid things and damage ourselves? No. Is it because we
ought to say no to our passions and desires, perhaps because they propose
immoral conduct to us? ‘No’ again. Aristotle’s reason is that the right and
good order between the different faculties of the soul is out of sync if we let
ourselves be steered blindly by our passions. In us, the ‘higher’ faculty of
practical reason must control and fashion the lower faculties. That control and
fashioning is lost when we are overwhelmed or, as kids, still steered by our
desires and feelings entirely. We miss out on our specifically human potential,
when we do not practice the excellences. All of them are anchored in our
rational soul, and their practice requires practical reason.
Why privilege virtues like
courage, moderation, justice, and friendship over fear, wanting everything
right now, or pursuing one’s self-interest at the expense of others, or living
in splendid solitude? Because, the passions or felt dispositions cause us to
act without choice. When we let that happen, we abandon ourselves and stop
being masters of ourselves. They have chosen for us when they put pressure on
us to enact them: to act out of anger or passion alone, to act to satisfy our
desire just because that desire wants it so. From Aristotle’s point of view the
question is: who is the master? Is it you, or is it your passion? Is it you, or
is it your desires? The good life, the ‘moral’ life is a life of mastery. We
need to master our passions. But we also need to be masters of ourselves. We
are masters of ourselves where we make rational choices. “In respect to the
excellences and the vices we are said not to be moved but to be disposed in a
particular way” (NE Reader p. 381, 1106a5).
Aren’t our feelings as
dignified a part of us as our reason? Why not declare that our feelings,
passions, desires and appetites do not overwhelm us, because they are ‘us’, at
least as much as our reason. Who would that ‘us’ be, in the first place? We are
our feelings, and we do not lose mastery when we give in to them. In that case
we are the masters through that part of us that belongs to our affective
faculties. The question is not, whether our affects or we are the masters. The
problem rather is: Shall we let ourselves be ruled by our reason or by our
feelings. What would Aristotle reply? He might argue that the rational and the
irrational elements of our soul are not at the same level, and therefore are
not equal players in a game where either the one or the other dominates us. Of
course, all the elements have their own excellences, the irrational elements as
well as the rational ones (NE p. 374, 1102b3). The decisive difference between
the rational and the irrational elements in our soul: the irrational faculties come without choice, whereas the rational
elements enable, even demand choice.
In choice, it is not just reason that chooses. We choose through reason. Reason
alone does not determine what we are to do (but: contemplative
excellence). Aristotle does not operate
with the dichotomy ‘reason vs. passion’. We moderns do. His alternative is:
activity of the soul under (some) choice vs. activity of the soul without
choice. In some cases, reason “persuades the irrational element by giving
advice or exhortation.” (From “On the Soul”).
Choice and Deliberation:
What is choice in a matter
where excellence is at stake? Let us assume that I am a freshman at UCI, start
Core, and realize that the instructor has chosen to teach Aristotle. I do not
understand a word of this philosophy. I begin to fear that Core will mess up
the stellar GPA I want to achieve at UCI. That fear proposes to me that I drop
the course. Now, following Aristotle, if I just let my fear dictate my
behavior, I stand badly with reference to my pathos. Fear, as we know,
will predominantly tell me to avoid the danger, which is the object of my fear.
If there is an excellence to be pursued, here, it is courage. Now, is courage
just to stay on and ignore the fear? A certain kind of rationality might
suggest that to me: I need the course; better to get it behind; I will somehow
muddle through; perhaps things will not be as bad as they now appear. But, if I
come down at the side of reason like this, I have not performed a proper moral
choice. I have done nothing that “makes a man good and makes me perform my work
well” (NE p. 382, 1106a22). I have done nothing to acquire the excellence of
courage. I have not been building character, more precisely: the character
trait of courage.
The Intermediate:
Excellence or virtue involves
choice, and that choice “must have the quality of aiming at an intermediate”
(NE p. 382, 1106b15) between extremes. Aristotle’s key formula:
“Excellence, then, is a state
concerned with choice, lying in a mean relative to us, this being determined by
reason and in the way in which the man of practical wisdom would determine it.
Now it is a mean between two vices, that which depends on excess, and that
which depends on defect” (NE Reader p. 383, 1107a1).
How does this work? Let us
try to unpack the formula. In our example, the excellence is courage. Our
choice is twofold: It is, on the one hand, the choice of courage as opposed to
the extremes, whatever they may be. It is, on the other hand, the choice of
that action which a better or worse enactment of courage. Let me wanting to be
brave. Do I then know what I ought to do? No way! “Matters concerning conduct
and questions of what is good for us – here: what counts as the right
courageous conduct have no fixity . . . account of the particular case is yet
more lacking in exactness” (EN Reader p. 377, 1104a4-6) How come, courage does
not come with a list of descriptions that align situations and the actions to
be taken: In case of . . . you will be brave if you . . .? The reason is that
there are two many different factors to be considered for a general policy
recommendation to be able to be on target. That target is the excellence of
courage! The same holds for friendship. Aristotle does not tell us what to do
in order to be a perfect friend. He does offer us orientation: friends help
each other. Unconditionally? No, help as requested by our addict friend may be
disastrous for the friend. We need to deliberate and use practical wisdom at
all times!
But how do these
intermediaries help me in my difficulty to opt in favor of courage and to
conceive of the right action in my situation of the difficult Core course?
First: the extremes. Abstractly, if courage is the mean as the right response
to fear, then cowardice is ‘not enough courage’, i.e. the defect of courage,
for it is the state of the soul of someone who lets him-/herself be controlled
by fear. (The coal on the bridge in the Fairy Tale?). But in that same
dimension - confronting a threatening
situation - there is another extreme. It is that of ignoring the danger and the
difficulty, or of rushing into the danger, reckless audaciousness (compare NE
Reader p. 384. 1107a32-1107b2). This misses out on courage by excessive
disregard for the danger and, I would say, for what talks to me in terms of my
fear: you may not be successful in that course.
Following Aristotle, I have
decided to be brave and to choose an intermediate course of action between
cowardice and disregard for my fear. But you can form an intermediate only if
you know the extremes. Cowardice, insensitivity to danger (Grimm’s fairy tale:
“The Young Man Who Went Out in Search of Fear”) do not tell me what kind of
action counts as one or the other vice. But “excellence both finds and chooses
that which is intermediate” (NE p. 383, 1107a5). But now I have a grid, and a
continuum of positions between the two poles of cowardice and audaciousness,
and I can try to compare different scenarios and actions as to where they put
me in that continuum. Why should it be cowardly to back off? It would perhaps
be cowardly if I simply drop, without weighing my chances of success. What of
the idea of muddling through, or just closing my eyes and stay on? That looks
like pure disregard of the danger. Did I weigh the danger concretely enough?
What are my chances of succeeding? If I know perfectly well that Aristotle and
I will be eternally without mutual understanding, then I perhaps better listen
to my fear. It tells me what my reason also tells me: this won’t work. On the
other hand: What if I am prepared to put in some extra work? That might
diminish the chances of failure. But is the course worth the effort? And there
still remains a risk I will not make it, or not do well. Personally, I think
that if we should also enter another excellence into the equation: healthy
pride, as a rational motive to pull through rather that out!
All this is called practical
deliberation. The extremes and the idea of an intermediate are just helps in
making up one’s mind in a rational way. I take fear seriously, but only if it
can gain approval by reason. Note that I have done two things simultaneously in
that deliberation: I have worked out what courage means for me in my situation.
The intermediate is always “relative to us” (NE Reader p. 382, 1106b5). Another
person, or a slight change in the situation might led to a different conclusion
about what courage means under the different circumstances. And I have
determined what my specific courageous action will be. I have chosen this
course of action as the intermediate one, avoiding cowardice and insensitivity
or audaciousness. In other words: I have enriched my experience of courage by
the case, ready, perhaps, to respond similarly in similar cases, or to argue
significant difference in a new deliberation.
I have tried to demonstrate
to you the openness of Aristotle’s practical rationality, but also the
habit-building and character-building nature of his procedure in the pursuit of
excellence. It is also a dealing with attitudes that deviate from the
excellence such as fear, and will fashioning, character building, quality for
me; for I have led my fear to be felt “at the right time, with reference to the
right object, towards the right people (me!), with the right aim, and in the
right way.” (NE Reader p. 383, 1106b20.)
Why be good by pursuing
excellences? What makes excellences good?
What if someone said: why
pursue excellences in my life, why not the vices? Why be truthful rather that
insincere? Why try to match the status one enjoys with the justification for
that status? Why not rather choose the pursuit of wealth or of pleasure as main
orientation of my life, and subordinate other pursuits to this central purpose?
What is the argument for the claim that such a person does not lead a good
life? What if he says, that he is living his idea of the right kind of life?
And a question of a second
order: What makes the excellences/virtues good, and the vices bad? Let us look
at Aristotle’s rejection of a moneymaking life first. (NE Reader p. 367,
1096a5-10). Where the acquisition of wealth is the dominant project in a life,
Aristotle says, there that life is undertaken under a compulsion. We may wonder
where the compulsion is when the life of money is a fundamental choice of an
agent. (Disney’s Uncle Scrooge McDuck!). But Aristotle really argues that the
compulsion lies elsewhere. Wealth is not a goal in itself. It is only a means
for something else. From our point of view this is probably a normative
statement: that is what the interest in wealth should be, for example to allow
a life of leisure that can be spent in contemplation. In Uncle Scrooge, money
has obviously become a goal in itself, a goal where possession and augmentation
confer pleasure. A true scrooge reverses this instrumental relation. For him
money becomes a goal in itself. From Aristotle’s point of view that is an
aberration. Wealth is not a primary good, like health, something we pursue
(also) for its own sake. It is not rational to desire wealth for its own sake.
Wealth should be no more than a means to an end different from wealth
itself. If that is the case, then a life
that puts the highest value on wealth puts itself under the constraint of the
things wealth can procure. Wealth is a conditional good. It is “merely useful and
for the sake of something else.” (NE Reader p. 367, 1196a6).
A problem Aristotle does not
address at this place: money can buy goods that are worth for their own sake,
like health or a life of contemplation. Money, as it functions in our
environment, is the generalized access to very different kinds of good. Does
that make it worth one’s while to pursue it for its own sake? I do not think
so.
How about a different
pursuit, the pursuit of pleasure? We are now asking whether such a life is not
a good life too. Or perhaps the only good life. Aristotle is again very short
in his rejection: For Aristotle, a life of pleasure – understood as a life of
enjoyment (NE Reader p. 366, 1095b17) – is a preference for a life suitable to
beasts. Aristotle seems to presuppose that practical reason aims at seizing
certain potentials we have, i.e. ‘excellences’. We begin to get a clearer
notion why only his excellences are good, and are the only real good things for
the pursuit of the good life. Pleasures may be something we pursue for their
own sake. That would, by the way, include the more beastly ones and the more
refined ones. But to be truthful or courageous or just or a friend to a friend
is not per se pleasurable, and in many cases unpleasurable in the sense of
fulfilling wishes and desires or material interests. If pleasure is the
ultimate measure for the good life, then these other excellences will not be
chosen. Aristotle could think like this: the pursuit of pleasure carries with
it a special and peculiar kind of dependence. I may be able to fashion my
pleasures, at least to some extent. But even if I were their master in that
respect, once they are in place, I will be the slave of my pleasures. I do not
choose my pleasure and what provides them, in the same way in which I choose to
be truthful, brave or just or a friend. The interest in pleasure always
manifests itself in form of a desire. And desires motivate to go after their
object. In cases of courage, truthfulness of justice we are the masters of both
the decision to let our life be guided by the virtue and to choose it as guide
in a given case, and we determine the object of the excellence in this
case. Our mastery coincides with our choice of the excellence. That choice
enables us to be masters in the application of the virtue, and to be masters of
ourselves in dealing with the resistances.
What do we take away from the
two negative cases for our question why the excellences designated by Aristotle
are good? First, unlike wealth, these excellences are not goods because they
are means towards something else. Excellences are chosen for their own sake and
for the sake of no other good (NE Reader p. 369/370, 1097a30-36). Why is
truthfulness good? Because we choose it for its own sake only, and not also for
the sake of anything else. This is of course not an argument! It is just saying
the same thing in the answer and in the question. We are only explicating the
goodness of the excellences, not giving an independent ground for their
goodness. In other words: the question what makes excellences good and vices
bad does not receive an independent answer, an answer that provides a reason
beyond of what the excellences are. You may be a little disappointed. Does the
philosopher have nothing more to offer for his ethics than an explication of
what we mean when we look for a ‘highest good’ what we mean, he says, is a good
that is good only for its own sake. But, then, Aristotle thinks that reason is
here at both sides: at the side of the object and at the side of the inquiry
into the object. The objects are the excellences. Reason has gains insight into
itself, and its unconditional character when it finds that the excellences are
autotelic goods. To articulate the highest goods is self-elucidation of
reason. Not self-grounding! To act under the guidance of the highest
goods is self-realization of reason.
I return to happiness before
we turn to the specific virtue of friendship. Aristotle starts his NE with the
form of the highest good, and works his way to the idea of choice and of the
intermediate. We have worked our way from choice, back to the highest good and
goods. Unlike wealth and money excellences are goods we choose for their own
sake. They are reason’s own tendency to become real and to fashion our lives,
simultaneously goods we need to make real by choosing them and by choosing
under their guidance. Is there something that unites all the excellences
without being a further purpose to which they all are means? Pleasure and
enjoyment do not qualify, in spite of the fact that we also seek pleasure for
its own sake (EN Reader p. 368, 1096b18). However refined, pleasure will always
be connected to the senses: sensuous pleasure, and the happiness based on
pleasure will not be shared by excellences.
Is there something all the
excellences share? (NE Reader p. 368, 1096b21-25). Aristotle thinks there is
such a common feature. And it is, again, happiness, but a happiness of a
specific kind. I quickly introduced it at the beginning. Aristotle calls it
“eudaimonia:” ‘to be be-spirited in the good way.’ Let us call it ‘moral
happiness’ in order to distinguish it from ‘sensuous happiness.’ What kind of a
feeling is ‘moral happiness? Aristotle calls it complete (NE Reader p. 369, 1097a31) and self-sufficient (NE Reader p. 370, 1097b7 & 15). The
completeness is the lack of dependence of the excellences on other things
justifying them, the fact that they are highest goods, not just pursued for the
sake of some other good. Self-sufficiency is “that which when isolated makes
life desirable and lacking in nothing.” (NE Reader p. 370, 1097b15). This is
close to what I have called ‘self-mastery’ earlier, or includes self-mastery.
Moral happiness also seems to be a feeling of plenitude. Of having or pursuing
something that makes one’s life worthwhile living: a good life. Living a life
that seeks to enact excellences thus confers a feeling of completeness and
self-sufficiency. Aristotle thinks that this is the purpose of man: “the kind
of life” that consists in “an activity or actions of the soul” implying a
rational principle” (choice of the intermediate between extremes), and the
purpose of a good human being to be the good and noble performance of these,
and . . .any action is well performed when it is performed in accordance with .
. . the best and most complete excellence,” “and that ‘in a complete life’” (NE
Reader p. 371, 1098 a12-20, citation modified). A (morally) happy man lives and
fares well” (NR p. 372, 1098b20). His life is “in itself pleasant.” (NE p. 373,
1099a5), whether he enjoys what he is doing or does not, also because he does
well what his most precious and dignified purpose is: to use reason.